i
UNIVERSITY OF JYVÄSKYLÄ
School of Business
What is Moral and (or) Ethical Leadership? A Descriptive
Interpretative Study of Concepts
Leadership, Pro-Graduate Thesis
October 2004
Author: Markus Ilomäki
Instructor: Anna-Maija Lämsä
ii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Table of Contents...........................................................................................................ii
1 Introduction............................................................................................................1
1.1 The Objective of the Study ............................................................................2
1.2 Research Problems.........................................................................................4
1.3 Reason and Contribution of the Study...........................................................4
1.4 The Approach and Methodology of Study.....................................................5
2 Attempting to Define Ethic(s), Moral and Leadership ........................................11
2.1 Developments in the Study of Leadership...................................................11
2.2 Defining Leadership.....................................................................................14
2.3 Distinguishing Ethic(s) and (or) Morality in Leadership.............................17
2.4 Ethic(s), Moral, Synonyms? ........................................................................20
2.5 Role of Deontology and Teleology..............................................................22
2.6 Altruism and Egoism ...................................................................................27
3 Ethical Leadership and Leadership Styles ...........................................................32
3.1 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Transactional and Transformational
Leadership................................................................................................................32
3.2 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Charismatic Leadership.........................37
3.3 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Servant Leadership................................38
3.4 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Post-industrial Leadership.....................42
3.5 The Moral Philosophy of Personalism and Leadership ...............................44
3.6 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Kantian Ethics .......................................47
3.7 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Directive Leadership .............................48
3.8 Models of Ethical Leadership ......................................................................50
4 Moral Leadership and Character..........................................................................54
4.1 Traditional Teleology and Virtue Ethics......................................................58
4.2 Character Development and the Human Factor HF.....................................62
4.2.1 Developing the Human Factor Concept...............................................69
4.2.2 Impact areas of the Human Factor .......................................................72
5 Discussion and Results ........................................................................................77
5.1 What is Moral and (or) Ethical Leadership?................................................78
5.2 Validity, Reliability and Credibility ............................................................82
5.3 Further Recommended Research .................................................................83
6 Conclusion ...........................................................................................................85
7 Bibliography ........................................................................................................87
iii
TABLE OF FIGURES
FIGURE 1 Interpretative Study of Concepts ................................................................7
FIGURE 2 The Conceptual Framework of the Study.................................................10
FIGURE 3 Forms of Altruistic and Egotistic Behaviour............................................29
FIGURE 4 A Model of Ethical Leadership by Edward Aronson ...............................52
FIGURE 5 Sources of Self-Transformation of Leaders and Followers......................58
FIGURE 6 The Human Factor Composition ..............................................................63
FIGURE 7 Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership MEDAL ....81
1
1 INTRODUCTION
What several European revolutions, two world wars and numerous
depressions could not do to London’s Barings Bank in more than 200 years,
one 28-yearold employee accomplished with a few computer keystrokes.
And the bank collapsed…management was alerted months ago to the
inadequacies of its oversight systems. But management chose to ignore that
advice, presumably because everyone seemed to benefit from the system as it
was (Mendonca 2001, 267)
Are we in need of moral and (or) ethical leadership? It is not hard to answer this
question and as time has passed it has become more or less a rhetorical question. All
one has to do is open the newspaper, turn on the radio or TV, to discover that
someone has had to step down or resign after unethical practices in business or
politics. It is not long ago that EU elected the French banker Jean-Claude Trichet to
head its central bank after a delay due to Mr. Trichet being tried for fraud in France.
Following this event Silvio Berlusconi received the EU presidency for the next six
months while corruption charges still persist on his head (BBC News). Some months
later Italian foods giant Parmalat suddenly files for bankruptcy because billions of
euros are missing from its books; the list goes on and on. It is clear that if moral and
ethical leadership is needed it is needed today more than ever.
The above examples are merely a few cases that have reached the media and crossed
the news barrier. Clearly majority of ethical and moral violations take place beyond
the sight of media and the authorities. It is not necessarily surprising for us then to
find out that in two US experimental studies “47% of top executives and 41% of the
controllers made fraudulent decisions that artificially inflated profits to increase their
promotion chances” (Mendonca 2001, 267). It is clear that what reaches the media is
a mere tip of the ice-berg.
It seems that the question, are we in need of moral and (or) ethical leadership? should
be changed to, how much are we in need of moral and ethical leadership? to which the
response most likely is, more than we can currently comprehend. Comprehending the
need seems to be the biggest problem especially in the world of business and politics,
as the previously cited examples show.
2
Comprehending the seriousness of the issue appears to be even more difficult. The
problem of comprehension in terms of moral and ethical leadership may be related to
the complexity of the topic and its unclear segmentation and conceptualization. There
is much talk about business ethics and moral and ethical leadership, but in many cases
it seems as if one were talking apples and oranges. It is also often difficult for the
practitioners involved to relate the moral and ethical leadership needs into real applied
terms in their life. In the following study the conceptual framework of moral and (or)
ethical leadership will be addressed and developed in such a way that even the
practitioner may comprehend the relationships of the different aspects and how to
proceed in addressing them.
1.1 The Objective of the Study
The primary objective of this study is to search for an answer to the question currently
at the lips of many professionals, academics and practitioners; the question being,
what is moral and (or) ethical leadership? To reach our objective interpretative study
of concepts is used as a method in developing the concepts (see, Takala & Lämsä
2001; Lämsä & Takala 2003).
The process of answering what is moral and (or) ethical leadership starts first at a very
elementary level in the first section by looking at the meanings and definitions of the
concepts of leadership, moral, ethical, and ethics as we understand them today. From
this clarification of the elements the study will then proceed further into the specific
dimensions (see figures 2 & 7).
Before proceeding into the moral and ethical dimensions we will address the topic of
leadership. This is due to the fact, that even after centuries of intense academic study
on leadership we still do not seem to have a consensus as to what leadership really is
and how to define it. This is also apparent in the writings of other researchers such as,
Kanungo and Mendonca (1996). Kanungo and Mendonca quote Bennis, who had this
to say about leadership in 1959:
3
Of all the hazy and confounding areas in social psychology, leadership theory
undoubtedly contends for top nomination. And, ironically, probably more
has been written and less known about leadership than about any other topic
in the behavioural sciences. Always, it seems the concept of leadership
eludes us or turns up in another form to taunt us again with its slipperiness
and complexity. (Kanungo & Mendonca 1996, 10)
In further reflection on the development of leadership research Kanungo and
Mendonca (1996) point that after three decades of research we have not become much
more enlightened as can be observed from the following quote by Kets de Vries
(1994):
As far as leadership studies go, it seems that more and more has been studied
about less and less, to end up ironically with a group of researchers studying
everything about nothing. It prompted one wit to say recently that reading
the current world of literature on leadership is rather like going through the
Parisian telephone directory while trying to read it in Chinese! (Kanungo &
Mendonca 1996, 11).
Ironically enough (with regards to Kets de Vries) we attempt to proceed
further here by adding morals and ethics to the study of leadership, and “naively”
pursuing in search of meanings, and comprehensions on two of the most controversial
topics of today. Since I have no desire to add to the Chinese version of the Parisian
telephone directory, but rather increase the clarity of its English version, the study
will remain at such a level at which it is able to contribute to a better understanding of
the Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership, and not to complicate
them further.
Even though many leadership researchers admit that the field of study is somewhat in
a crisis, I still agree with Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) in that a significant amount
of information has been gained by past research, and that research in the field should
continue and not be given up. Society can significantly gain from the more recent
developments in the field such as moral and (or) ethical leadership. The field of study
is most likely in turmoil for a reason and it is perhaps a time to shift some of the
boundaries and redefine concepts; separate and analyse some areas, and bring
synthesis to others.
4
1.2 Research Problems
As discussed in the introduction the primary objective of the study is to search for an
answer to the question “what is moral and (or) ethical leadership”. In the process
other secondary questions will be touched on to expand the definition.
Primary Research Question (PRQ) for the study:
1). What is Moral and (or) Ethical in Leadership, and are the concepts the same?
We tend to use the words moral and ethical as synonyms in daily dialogues, as well as
in academic discourse. This is the reason why the terms appear separately in the
research question.
1.3 Reason and Contribution of the Study
On a global scale we have seen a dramatic increase in the level of interest towards the
topic in the last few years (for obvious reasons), especially in North-America (US and
Canada), where most of the research on leadership, and moral and (or) ethical
leadership takes place.
Overall the topic of moral and (or) ethical leadership has been given relatively little
attention in academic writing and thus should be pursued to complement the study
and research done on leadership.
The current direction of leadership research is another significant reason to pursue
moral and ethical leadership as a field of study. This is due to the fact that much of
the later modern and post-modern leadership theory has adopted moral and ethical
aspects as part or the “heart” of their leadership concept.
Summary of Reasons:
1. Novel topic in the Finnish research context.
2. Current public demand in the topic area.
3. The global focus of leadership research shifting towards moral and ethical
dimensions.
5
This study attempts to bring significant theoretical contributions to the field of moral
and ethical leadership, by separating and making a distinction between the different
concepts of moral leadership (specifically pertaining to character and the conduct of
the leader), ethical leadership (specifically pertaining to the leaders behaviour and the
principles of human duty), and leadership ethics (specifically pertaining to the code of
ethics). A further result of the above objectives will be introduced later as the
MEDAL model of Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership
(MEDAL), (see figure 7 for more details).
1.4 The Approach and Methodology of Study
Approaching the research question is done first by analysing the aspects of moral,
ethic (s), and leadership and their definitions and meanings separately, so as to define
the elementary building blocks. After defining our building blocks (moral, ethic(s),
and leadership) the study will proceed by identifying any possible distinctions and
clarification so as to acknowledge possibilities, interpretation and expansion
according to the research method selected. Finally the different ethical dimensions of
leadership are developed further, with respect to specific leadership styles that are
currently at the centre of the debate of moral and (or) ethical leadership.
Due to the nature of the study my approach on the topic is for the most part a
theoretical interpretation for the reason that the answer to our research question lies in
the study of ethics, leadership, and the humanity. These topics are extremely
challenging due to their nature, which is multidimensional and contains subject matter
that is prone to controversy and subjectivity. Due to this multidimensionality it is not
possible to give a comprehensive answer as to what moral and ethical leadership is,
but rather to provide a starting point and an introduction from which further research
can be developed. For this reason both analysis and synthesis will take place, and
concepts (at times) are taken and introduced to the reader without full synthesis and
integration into a clear conclusion. However this is part of the hermeneutic spiral and
one must jump out of if at one point maybe to return later.
Due to the very basic nature of the study and its purpose in describing and defining
moral and ethical leadership, many of the current more developed research methods
6
were found inappropriate (discourse analysis, narrative analysis, etc.) at this point.
Originally discourse analysis was considered as a method and an approach, but as the
research progressed it soon became clear that interpretative study of concepts could
add more value to the research process (for methodological framework to be covered
see figure 1). It is true that significant opportunities for the use of more advanced
methods, such as discourse analysis exist within the topic area. However these
opportunities require a different approach where one is not trying to define, describe
and understand moral and ethical leadership, but for example describe the moral and
ethical leadership discourses found in today’s business news or organizational texts.
The approach of this study is qualitative, and its logic of scientific reasoning is
somewhat abductive. Due to the elementary nature of the study the method used here
is descriptive interpretative study of concepts as applied to the recent academic
writings on the topic of moral and (or) ethical leadership. This is to say that the study
will look at what has been written on moral and ethical leadership, which is
fortunately still at this point a manageable amount of material. The analysis will then
concentrate on how moral and (or) ethical leadership is defined, described, and
comprehended in the academic literature and what are, or how should the concepts of
moral and ethical leadership be developed.
7
FIGURE 1 Interpretative Study of Concepts
Source: Lämsä & Takala 2003
There are four different types of interpretative study of concepts approaches, 1)
Heuristic interpretative study of concepts, 2) Theory-oriented interpretative study of
concepts, 3) Descriptive interpretative study of concepts, and 4) Critical interpretative
study of concepts (see, Takala & Lämsä, 2001, 385). Out of the four different
approaches the descriptive interpretative study of concepts was selected as it fits best
with the primary objective of the study.
The descriptive interpretative study of concepts is aimed at increasing the
understanding of a concept or concepts (Takala & Lämsä, 2001). The objective of
this type of a study is “to find, describe and interpret the entity of meanings” (Lämsä
2003). In the descriptive interpretative study of concepts “a researcher aims at
describing and clarifying the significations given to a concept” which in this case is
moral and (or) ethical leadership (Lämsä 2003).
The study follows the dialectics of the interpretative study of concepts where one
moves between the stages of 1) intuition, 2) new concepts and imagination, and 3)
reflective thinking (Takala & Lämsä 2001, 384; Lämsä & Takala 2003).
The Method of the
Interpretative
Study of Concepts
The data and the
data gathering of the
interpretative study
of concepts
The research
process of the
interpretative
study of
The theoretical
viewpoint of the
interpretative
study of concepts
Different types
of the
interpretative
study of
8
The dialectics of the interpretative study of concepts can be examined from
the aspect of cognition science (cf. Tenbrunsel et al 1997). From this
perspective the interpretative study of concepts can be defined as a way of
using concepts and their meanings in creating internal models – thought
structures – based on prior data (Lämsä & Takala 2001, 387; 2003).
The objective of this study is to follow the creative dialectic process in analysing the
data, applying intuition, imagination and reflective thinking to it, so as to see if new
concepts, ways of understanding or organizing are, can be, or need to be formed.
The data of the study consists of written texts in the area of moral and ethical
leadership. This approach being called, interpretative research based on textual data
(Takala & Lämsä 2001). In this approach the researcher does not interact with the
producers of the data, which is the case in interpretative empirical research. Since the
data exists independent of the researcher it is termed natural data.
The approach taken towards science in this study is, that of science being careful
thinking and a feeling of knowing (Takala & Lämsä 2001). This approach depends
heavily on a strong emphasis on the perspective of individual psychology. The view
of scientific knowledge is defined rather by the research community than the specific
individual researcher involved. Science is further seen as a dynamic living thing
among the discourses of the scientific community (Takala & Lämsä 2001).
It is pointed out that the “processing of the research process of the interpretative study
of concepts is a so-called hermeneutic circle (Lämsä 2003). This causes the
researcher to be prepared to constantly reformulate his/her research process as the
interaction of his/her ideas and the data/text takes place. This hermeneutic circle is
sometimes understood as a spiral having no end, and thus requiring, as Takala and
Lämsä point out (2001), the researcher to jump of the spiral at some point when
“adequately interesting and relevant” interpretations have been reached (Lämsä &
Takala 2003).
Leadership styles, their differences and similarities, as well as their relation to morals
and ethics, will be looked at in the form of parallel exegetic study in section three.
Later on in the study a more hermeneutic approach may be appropriate as one would
want to move from trying to explain to trying to understand. Moral and ethical
9
leadership, as many social sciences, can only be mastered to an extent by exegetic
study in trying to explain the phenomena. Further expertise requires a hermeneutic
approach to provide understanding to the aspects that do not necessarily follow
rational guidelines. Moral and ethical leadership may in many cases appear very
irrational and confusing to many young post-modern leaders.
From the perspective of knowledge interests the study will take an approach different
from the traditional approaches (technical, practical/interpretative, and critical). This
approach will be something along the lines of what Niiniluoto proposes called
theoretic knowledge interest (Anttila 2003). According to this approach the function
of theoretic knowledge interest is to interpret aspects of reality without the traditional
interpretation and control obligations, by using current theories as a the tool. The
motive according to Niiniluoto is the intellectual need of human beings to analyse the
surrounding world around them, and to reach truthful information about it. As for this
study, pursuing the need to analyse and comprehend the concepts of moral and (or)
ethical leadership as they exist in the surrounding world in which we live and are
called to make moral and (or) ethical choices at an ever increasing pace.
The conceptual framework of the study consists of three levels and proceeds in the
following way, 1) definitional level, 2) behavioural level, and 3) personal level (see
figure 2 for more detail). In these levels the study attempts to synthesize the concepts
of 1) leadership and moral and (or) ethical, 2) leadership styles and ethics and codes
of ethics, and 3) leader character and moral and virtues. Now we will move on to the
definitional level.
10
FIGURE 2 The Conceptual Framework of the Study
Leadership Moral & Ethic(s)
Moral and Ethical Leadership Dimensions, Figure 2.1
• Moral Leadership
• Ethical Leadership
• Leadership Ethics
Leadership Styles Ethical & Codes
of Ethics
Leader Character Morals & Virtues
Moral Leaders Character Assesment and Development:
• Virtues
• Human Factor
Leadership Styles and Ethics:
• Transformational Leadership
• Transactional Leadership
• Charismatic Leadership
• Servant Leadership
• Directive Leadership
• Postindustrial Leadership
Definitional (conceptual) Level: Interaction of Leadership, Ethic
and Moral
Personal (character) Level: Interaction of Leader Character,
Morals and Virtues
Behavioral (style) Level: Interaction of Leadership Styles, Ethics,
Values and Codes of Ethics
11
2 ATTEMPTING TO DEFINE ETHIC(S), MORAL AND
LEADERSHIP
To start the interpretative process, the concepts of ethic(s), moral and leadership need
to be carefully analysed and developed. This is done so as to introduce and provide
understanding on these topics before moving on to rebuilding them. It is clear that the
topics are extremely difficult to grasp by nature, and as a warning this is not an
attempt at a comprehensive definition, reaching all aspects of leadership morality and
ethics, but merely a prelude in this specific context.
2.1 Developments in the Study of Leadership
To set the stage, we will quickly outline some of the history of leadership research
and look at how leadership has developed during the past century and reached its
current position. This is important as our perception of what moral and (or) ethical
leadership is, depends heavily on how and what leadership is perceived to be, and
what constitutes leadership.
In the early 20th century leadership research was purely focused on discovering traits
or characteristics that were identifiable to leaders rather than followers. In the
beginning this type of leadership study was mostly concerned about different kinds of
“physical characteristics (e.g., height, appearance), personality (e.g., self-esteem,
dominance, emotional stability), and ability (general intelligence, verbal fluency,
creativity, social insight)” (Yukl 1989, 173). As it became more evident that traits
could not be identified to have a clear connection to leadership performance the focus
of research shifted in the late 1940’s to behavioural or style research.
If we are to take the standpoint that the aspects of morality and ethics cannot be
mutually exclusive with respect to leadership, we can see why the traits would have
lacked a constant connection to leadership performance. Here we assume that there is
no performance unless leadership is moral and (or) ethical. At this point there are
some hands up in the class room raising the question of Stalin and Hitler and why
12
they would not be considered powerful leaders as they clearly were able to deeply
influence people and amass large amounts of followers. The question here is between
what we consider good leadership (also moral and ethical), (see, Drouillard 1996) and
bad leadership (in many cases amoral and unethical). Hitler and Stalin were powerful
leaders but they were not great leaders (containing the assumption that a great leader
would also need to be a good leader). In other words Hitler and Stalin were powerful
bad leaders who were able to have a deep influence on their followers and gain a large
following, which in turn enabled them to further practice their bad leadership by
killing millions of people. We then make the case here, that from our perspective
leadership itself can be considered dependent on whether it is moral and (or) ethical.
When referring to leadership throughout this study we mean it to be good (moral and
(or) ethical) leadership.
It is also worth making the distinction that in the trait approach to leadership we are
not focused on actions (doing) but on traits and characteristics which are not
dependent on whether we are doing anything, rather us being something. Here then
the moral and (or) ethical dimension of the leadership is applied differently depending
whether our perception of leadership is focused on actions (doing) or characteristics
(being). As we look at the behavioural approach more carefully we can see how our
qualifications change along side of our perceptions.
Behavioural or style “approach essentially states that it is what leaders do that makes
them effective.” (Aronson 2001, 245). Behavioural studies have traditionally had two
subcategories, one focused on the nature of managerial work and the other focused on
activity patterns of how managers spend their time (Yukl 1989, 8). In the late 1960’s
again it became evident that behavioural and style studies were not telling the whole
story and interest in research started shifting to the situation and conditions under
which leadership took place. This type of leadership study then became called the
contingency approach.
After the first major work of Fielder’s contingency theory (for more in-depth see
Fielder 1967) situational leadership study quickly became very popular and produced
multiple theories such as “the path-goal theory of House (for more in-depth see House
1973), situational leadership of Hersey and Blanchard (for more in-depth see Hersey
13
& Blanchard 1969), and Kerr and Jermier’s (for more in-depth see Jermier 1978)
leadership substitutes”; little later Vroom and Yetton (for more in-depth see Vroom
and Yetton 1973) also came out with their theory concentrating on leader’s decision –
making role behaviours ranging from autocratic to consultative (Aronson 2001, 245).
As the 1980’s came, the contingency theories lost interest, as it was felt that they were
limiting the research only to the supervisory situation of small groups, whereas, more
and more researchers wanted to look at a bigger picture; taking into account the whole
organization. This paved the way to what became called the “new leadership
perspective”, and in this new leadership perspective “researchers explored the
charismatic leadership phenomenon…and related it to the transformational and
transactional leadership influence processes postulated by Burns (1978)” (Aronson
2001, 246).
As we move from the behavioural perspective to contingency theory we arrive at a
situation where our focus in terms of leadership has shifted from behaviour to the
context. From the moral and ethic(s) perspective however, one cannot follow this
shift as the success or failure of the moral and (or) ethical leadership is still dependent
on behaviour regardless of the operational context.
More specifically the main leadership theories currently under discussion are
charismatic and transformational leadership, with significantly more emphasis paid on
the latter. Another theory which escapes our history, but which is of significant
interest when investigating ethical and (or) moral leadership is Robert K. Greenleaf’s
“servant leadership”. New theories or what we might call post-modern theories have
also emerged such as Joseph C. Rost's post-industrial leadership. These theories work
well with moral and (or) ethical leadership research because of their behavioural
focus. The most relevant leadership theories with respect to moral and ethical
leadership will be discussed in a separate section later on.
With this brief background on the developments in leadership research we will move
on to address the definition of leadership more specifically. We will take a look at
how the definition of leadership has developed in the past century, so as to be able to
establish a working definition of leadership for this study before moving to the moral
and (or) ethic(s) aspects.
14
2.2 Defining Leadership
As Yukl points out the word “leadership” is a word that has been taken out of the
common vocabulary and applied to professional contexts (Yukl, 1989). Thus the
word leadership is frequently applied to many different contexts without defining it
first, thus causing confusion. Another problem arises as the term “leadership” is often
defined in very different ways by different individuals, to the extent that after
reviewing leadership literature, Stogdill concluded that “There are almost as many
definition of leadership as there are persons who have attempted to define the concept
(Yukl 1989, p. 2). Bennis further noted in one of his early articles (1959) that:
Always, it seems, the concept of leadership eludes us or turns up in another
form to taunt us again which its slipperiness and complexity. So we have
invented an endless proliferation of terms to deal with it…and still the
concept is not sufficiently defined (Yukl 1989, 2).
Another factor further contributing to the confusion is the inclusion of other less
precise terms, such as, “power, authority, management, administration, control, and
supervision” to the phenomena of leadership (Yukl 1989, 2).
To start out, let us consider a few definitions of leadership and partly the historical
development of the leadership definition, so as not to make the common mistake Yukl
is referring to.
Recently the Journal of Business Strategy (2003) published a brief article on the
definitions of leadership. The article also concluded that there were significant
differences in the definitions where some seek to “emphasize the collaborative nature
of leadership, while others see an imperative to preserve the distance between leaders
and followers” (Townsend & Bennis, 2003). The unifying view among the
definitions was however, that leaders are individuals who take on themselves
challenges that no one else is willing to take. Even though Warren Bennis noted
earlier that the concept of leadership eludes him, he has provided his own definition
of leadership here as follows:
15
Leadership is the wise use of power. Power is the capacity to translate
intention into reality and sustain it (Townsend & Bennis, 2003, 48).
To continue the thought to the realm of moral and (or) ethical leadership we can
further state that with power comes responsibility and accountability, and with
responsibility and accountability come moral and (or) ethical responsibility and
accountability resulting in something called good or bad leadership (see, Drouillard
1996) or leadership and non-leadership. Following this logic it is clear that morality
and ethic(s) has a significant role to play in leadership and even whether someone’s
behaviour can be considered to be leadership (by this logic Hitler and Stalin can be
and often are disqualified as leaders). This shows that it may even be impossible to
attempt on a universal definition of leadership, bringing up the question (and
argument) whether leadership can exist at all without it being moral and (or) ethical
leadership? It is clear that the definition of leadership appears to be extremely
dependent on the aspects of what we will still here call moral and ethical.
For contrast it is useful to take a look at how the definition of leadership has
developed over time and map out some of its direction. Joanne B. Ciulla (1998) has
done exactly this and in her book “Ethics the Heart of Leadership” she lists a
chronology of leadership definitions from 1920’s to 1990’s in the following way.
1920s [Leadership is] the ability to impress the will of the leader on those
led and induce obedience, respect, loyalty, and cooperation.
1930s Leadership is a process in which the activities of many are organized
to move in a specific direction by one.
1940s Leadership is the result of an ability to persuade or direct men, apart
from the prestige or power that comes from office or external circumstances.
1950s [Leadership is what leaders do in groups.] The leader’s authority is
spontaneously accorded him by his fellow group members.
1960s [Leadership is] acts by a person that influence other persons in a
shared direction.
1970s Leadership is defined in terms of discretionary influence.
Discretionary influence refers to those leader behaviours under control of the
leader which he may vary from individual to individual.
1980s Regardless of the complexities involved in the study of leadership, its
meaning is relatively simple. Leadership means to inspire others to
undertake some form of purposeful action s ad determined by the leader.
16
1990s Leadership is an influence relationship between leaders and followers
who intend real changes that reflect their mutual purposes. (Ciulla 1998, 11)
After analysing this recent historical development of the definition of leadership
Ciulla also notes that, “where the definitions differ is… particularly in terms of their
implications for the leader-follower relationship” (Ciulla, 1998). In other words the
controversy today and in for the past decade has focused on the area of how leaders
get people to do the things they want them to do. How to “impress, organize,
persuade, influence, and inspire” followers to move in a specific direction (Ciulla,
1998). Further Ciulla notes that the definitions of 1920’s, 1970’s and 1980’s have
authoritarian elements where as the definitions of 1940’s, 1950’s, and 1960’s imply “a
non-coercive, participatory, and democratic relationship” between leaders and their
followers.
When taking into account the brief spectrum of definitions presented here, it is
evident that they are not mutually exclusive when viewed from the perspective of
morals and (or) ethics. On the one hand we have the definitions of leadership that
focus on the action, the how to “impress, organize, persuade, influence, and inspire”
others. In this case the qualifying criteria for leadership, the moral and (or) ethic(s)
microscopes is applied to the specific actions in question. On the other hand we have
an interactive, participatory and relationship oriented focus to leadership in which the
moral and (or) ethic(s) microscopes is applied to the interaction and the relationship
and the moral and (or) ethic(s) of this interaction or relationship. To sum up we have
focuses of action as well as interaction to take into account.
As a result when looking from the moral and (or) ethical angle, moral and (or) ethical
leadership is not dependent on the definition and can work irrespective of how
leadership is defined (but not the other way around). However, it would be
unnecessarily restrictive to adopt a working definition of leadership that would focus
purely on the authoritative actions of an individual to define their leadership. Thus it
is wise to adopt a more comprehensive definition where actions, other behaviours,
interaction and the relationship are all taken into account. When talking about moral
and (or) ethical leadership it is worth making the point that we are not restricted to
just doing (actions, interaction, etc.), but also the non-behavioural aspect of being
(character) constitutes a part of moral and (or) ethical leadership.
17
Having stated our approach in the above way we can adopt a working definition of
leadership from the 1990’s as it is quoted by Ciulla (1998).
Leadership is an influence relationship between leaders and followers who
intend real changes that reflect their mutual purposes. (Ciulla 1998, p.11)
Having defined leadership, the study can now move on to a more detailed study of the
moral and (or) ethical aspects of leadership, and how to approach and define it, so as
to fully answer our main research question; what is moral and (or) ethical leadership?
2.3 Distinguishing Ethic(s) and (or) Morality in Leadership
What do we mean by ethic(s) and moral in the first place and can we consider them to
be synonyms as is often done? Most academic writers in the area of moral and (or)
ethical leadership use the two terms as if they were synonyms, even though they
acknowledge some of the differences. If differences are recognized would it therefore
be beneficial to moral and (or) ethical leadership research if distinctions were clearly
made between the terms, which would allow further development of the concepts of
moral and ethical leadership.
The review of the terms moral and ethic(s) are based on academic literature (see,
Ciulla 1998, Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, and Frankena 1973) on moral and (or)
ethical leadership, The Blackwell Encyclopedic Dictionary of Business Ethics (see,
Werhane & Freeman 1997, 248), and the Oxford English dictionary (see, Oxford
English Dictionary 2004). As a result we begin outlining and distinguishing the
conceptual framework starting with the concept of ethical, ethic and ethics.
Starting from the very basics we first take a look at how the Oxford English
Dictionary (OED) defines ethic(s) and morality.
18
Ethic, a1. and n2:
Relating to morals. Of an author or literary work: Treating of moral
questions, and of ethics as a science. Characterized by ‘ethos.
The science of morals; cf. 2. A scheme of moral science.
(Oxford English Dictionary OED 2003).
Ethics: a. the science of morals; b. a scheme of moral science.
The science of morals; the department of study concerned with the principles
of human duty. A treatise on the science; spec. that of Aristotle. As discrete
plural: Ethical maxims or observations.
In narrower sense, with some qualifying word or phrase: a. The moral
principles or system of a particular leader or school of thought.
The moral principles by which a person is guided. The rules of conduct
recognized in certain associations or departments of human life. (Oxford
English Dictionary OED 2003).
The OED spells out the definition of ethics in the way that many of us understand
ethics, as the principles regarding our duty as humans. Aronson (2001) defines it as
follows, “Ethics is essentially the study of standards for determining what behaviour
is good and bad or right and wrong.” This definition and understanding, is also
associated to ethics in the other contexts that we are most familiar with such as
business ethics or corporate ethics. Frankena (1973) defines ethics as “a branch of
philosophy; it is moral philosophy or philosophical thinking about morality, moral
problems and moral judgements.” Meaning that in this context of philosophy the
morality is not universal or absolute, but rather relative and open to debate and
change.
As noted by Jan Narveson in The Blackwell Encyclopedic Dictionary of Business
Ethics, ethics in a narrower sense “applies to most of the moral philosophy of earlier
time”, and is concerned with norms of conduct of people in social groupings
(Werhane & Freeman 1997, 248). As we broaden the concept however we should
make note of three aspects, first an aspect of “we” where “ethics has never been
entirely self-addressed, but rather is a general inquiry” (Werhane & Freeman 1997,
248). Second there is a normative aspect of “should”, concerning “what to do, what
1 Symbol a standing for adjective
2 Symbol n standing for noun
19
would be good or bad, right or wrong, wise or unwise” (Werhane & Freeman 1997,
248). Thirdly there is an aspect of “do” that is also concerned with character and
“what we should be like, rather than the question of which actions we should
perform.” With respect to the definition of ethics it has to be acknowledged that when
defining ethics in its broader sense we can find conceptual separation into different
categories already as demonstrated above (Werhane & Freeman 1997, 248). However
even though this separation is perhaps noted on a mental level it is not used or
reflected in writing about the topic in such a way that it would bring clarity to the
study of moral and (or) ethical leadership. Thus it is suggested here that there should
be further development of the concepts and dimensions.
We can raise questions concerning these concepts and dimensions and whether moral
leadership already falls under ethical leadership or is perhaps an impossibility as a
term. Further questions may also arise concerning how narrow or broad these terms
and concepts are and whether there is justification for them to stand independently.
Moving on to the question of moral(s), how then do we understand and define
moral(s)? Again the Oxford English Dictionary helps us in this by defining morals
the following way:
Moral, a:
Relating to, affecting, or having influence on a person's character or conduct,
as distinguished from his or her intellectual or physical nature.
Of an action: having the property of being right or wrong, or good or evil;
voluntary or deliberate and therefore open to ethical appraisal.
Of a person, etc.: capable of moral action; able to choose between right and
wrong, or good and evil.
Of knowledge, an opinion, etc.: relating to the nature and application of the
distinction between right and wrong, or good and evil.
Of a feeling: arising from an apprehension or sense of the goodness or
badness of an action, character, etc.
Of or relating to human character or behaviour considered as good or bad; of
or relating to the distinction between right and wrong, or good and evil, in
relation to the actions, desires, or character of responsible human beings;
ethical. (Oxford English Dictionary OED 2003).
20
Now as we look at the definitions of morals we should identify a few things. First of
all they are concerned with action, as well as, the judgement of good or evil, right or
wrong. Second they are associated in many cases with a person’s character. For
example, one having a moral character or an immoral character, thus morals
becoming a question of character. We may not however, consider someone to have
an ethical character as ethics is not directly associated with character, but rather set
principles of behaviour or conduct. Morals with respect to character go a level deeper
than ethics they are more personal.
One can make a statement that someone demonstrates moral leadership, meaning that
that person possesses a high moral character and thus in their relationships and
interactions with others casts an influence on them (thus demonstrating moral
leadership). Morality with respect to leadership could be considered innate to
character in many respects, thus differentiating it from ethical leadership.
From a conceptual perspective it appears that there is reasonable justification here for
further development of the aspects of moral and ethical with respect to leadership.
2.4 Ethic(s), Moral, Synonyms?
As we have established it is clear that both ethic(s) and moral do overlap to some
extent and this is the reason that has enabled or caused them to be used as synonyms.
As we already mentioned, it would be beneficial to leadership if a separation between
the two was made allowing for a deeper insight into the constructs of moral and
ethical leadership.
This conflict brings one in front of a difficult conceptual decision, when trying to find
out and describe what ethical or moral leadership is. With respect to leadership
should the terms ethical and moral be used as synonyms or not? The easy way out
would be to decide in favour of using them as synonyms and thus not having to define
them separately, this however, would not help in bringing further understanding,
clarity and coherence to the study of moral and ethical leadership, nor is this in
accordance to our method of descriptive interpretative study of concepts. Thus I
21
choose not to use the terms moral and (or) ethical leadership as synonyms; in other
words I choose to acknowledge that there is a distinct difference that should be
acknowledged. After further research and discourse on the differences, this
distinction may prove beneficial to the field of leadership study. This distinction
could in the long run, help our understanding of the aspects of ethical and moral
leadership.
From the previously given definitions it is clear that even though parallel in some
respect the terms ethic(s) and moral are very different in other respects. As already
note, ethic or ethics relates more to the science or scheme of morals and to the
principles of human duty, where as, morality relates more to a persons character or
conduct.
The above distinction between ethic(s) and moral would be one worth making in the
context of leadership as well, where moral leadership pertains to the persons character
and conduct and the leadership that flows out of this character and conduct; while
ethical leadership would pertain to the leaders actions with respect to the principles of
human duty and moral science. It could be argued, that especially due to the
confusion about the meaning (or meanings) of “ethical leadership” it is not only
desirable that the distinction be made but absolutely necessary. The areas relating to
the moral leader’s character and conduct, and the ethical leaders accordance to
principles of human duty and moral science are in themselves more than sufficient
areas of research to even provide a new school of thought. It would be hard to argue
that we do not need it.
After making distinctions between the terms of ethic(s) and moral, I would suggest
further separation in terms of the broader concepts, or the specific areas of study. The
areas of study could be identified as “moral leadership”, “ethical leadership” and
“leadership ethics”.
The reader should however note that the mainstream understanding and practice is to
use the two terms moral and ethical as synonyms (Ciulla, 1998, 2003; Kanungo &
Mendonca, 1996) and in some cases in this thesis that may even be the case as we will
not take the liberty of trying to interpret which one an author is intending to have used
22
while elaborating on “moral leadership ethics”. Some authors as Kanungo and
Mendonca (1996) also note ethics pertaining to rules of conduct and morals pertaining
to character but still associate them as synonyms. Frankena (1973) also makes the
distinction that ethics is “sometimes used as just another word for “morality,” and
sometimes to refer to the moral code or normative theory of an individual or group”.
As I will not intend or be able to bring any kind of finality or consensus to this issue
here, but simply to note that this is an issue that perhaps requires study and a response
from the authorities on the subject.
After having further developed the concept of moral and ethical leadership into moral
leadership, ethical leadership and leadership ethics, we also have to note that this has
an effect on our approach to the primary research question what is moral and ethical
leadership? We must acknowledge that sublevels are created under the primary
research question where moral leadership and leadership ethics are discussed in more
detail and their definitions further developed in the mind of the reader.
In this study there will be three ways the above terms will be used. For the most part
of the study when talking about mainstream ethical leadership both terms ethical and
moral will be mentioned. When discussing the topic in the section on character and
character development however, the term moral leadership will be used. And finally
whenever there are direct quotations the most likely term to appear will be ethical
leadership.
2.5 Role of Deontology and Teleology
In trying to discover what moral and (or) ethical leadership is, it is important to try to
understand how an ethical act is defined, and thus, what constitutes moral or ethical
behaviour. In the literature on ethics, there are several different approaches to
defining whether behaviour or an act is moral or ethical and what can be considered
moral or ethical behaviour. (See, Aronson 2001 and Frankena 1973). The main
theoretical perspectives presented here provide a foundation for further analysis and
understanding of moral and (or) ethical leadership. In this section we will take a
23
closer look at the following topics, deontology, teleology, utilitarianism, egoism,
altruism.
In the writings of business ethics there are two perspectives that are most commonly
discussed in terms of behaviour, actions and their effects; deontology and teleology.
In trying to answer what moral and (or) ethical leadership is, it is beneficial for us to
establish what these theories of ethics are, and see what their contribution is to the
overall debate. By doing this we are able to further define moral and (or) ethical
leadership and to understand the different considerations that need to be taken into
question.
Deontological theories hold that there are other considerations which make an action
or a rule to be right and that the rightness or goodness of it is not wholly dependent on
its consequences, but rather the moral obligation (Frankena 1973, 15). Deontological
theories acclaim that there are specific features of the acts themselves that make them
ethical, these being other than the non-moral value being brought into existence.
Examples of this could be as Frankena points out “the fact that it keeps a promise, is
just, or is commanded by God or by the state.” Aronson put this all very clearly in
stating that deontology “may be described as the theory of study of moral obligation.”
(Aronson 2001, 248).
Deontological ethics considers a leader’s actions to have intrinsic moral
status. An act is considered moral when it is performed with a sense of
obligation or when it stems from a sense of duty guided by pure reason
(Kanungo 2001, 260).
Deontology or the study of moral obligation, then, can be divided into two main
categories, rule deontology and act deontology. Rule deontology pertains to a view
that “in all circumstances individuals should follow a set of predetermined standards
or rules, so that behaviour is ethical or unethical not as a consequence of the action,
but as compared to the standards themselves” (Aronson 2001, 248). Further Aronson
emphasises that the ethical judgement is concerned about the general principles,
which may be constructed from a set of more specific guidelines of how people
should behave in specific situations.
24
Frankena gives the statement, “We ought always to tell the truth” as an example of a
fairly concrete rule in terms of rule deontology (Frankena 1973, 17). According to
Frankena’s thinking, Samuel Clarke, Richard Price, Thomas Reid, W.D. Ross and
Immanuel Kant can be classified as either rule deontologist or act deontologist. He
points out that when “conscience” is used as the guide or standard of morality one can
be classified either rule or act deontologist, with the separation of conscience
providing the particular rules in the first case and making the individual judgements in
the second case.
Act deontology according to Frankena “maintain that the basic judgments of
obligation are all purely particular ones like, “In this situation I should do so and so,”
and that general ones like, “We ought always to keep our promises” are unavailable,
useless, or at best derivative from particular judgements” (Frankena 1973, 16).
In act deontology, “people act ethically according to their norms, but this is
limited to particular behaviours, implying that there may be exceptions to the
rule” (Aronson 2001, 248).
In the extreme case according to Frankena (1973) one must “decide separately in each
particular situation what is the right or obligatory thing to do, without appealing to
any rules and also without looking to see what will promote the greatest balance of
good over evil for one-self or the world.” Here at the extreme one can see the
separation of act deontology from rule deontology; having made the distinction let us
now take a look at teleology.
Teleology is the study of the created non-moral value and its measurement.
Teleological perspectives are outcome oriented and stress “the outcome, as opposed to
the intent of individual behaviour” (Aronson 2001, 248). In terms of teleological
ethics, a leader’s actions as such have no moral status, as it is considered that only the
outcome (the ends) determine the morality or lack of morality of the leadership
demonstrated (Kanungo 2001). By this logic George W. Bush is free to invade Iraq
even without grounds for doing so, as long as the outcome and the end result is good
(this could include restoration of justice, freedom, safety and quality of life).
25
As Aronson points out there are several classifications of teleological theories in
academic literature, however, the most significant ones for discussion in our case of
leadership ethics would be the theories of ethical egoism, act utilitarianism and rule
utilitarianism.
A teleological theory holds to the perspective that “the basic or ultimate criterion or
standard of what is morally right, wrong, obligatory, etc. is the non-moral value that is
brought into being” (Frankena 1973, 14). By this we mean the comparative
quantitative balance of non-moral good over evil. Aronson puts this well in his
interpretation of Frankena noting that “an act is moral if it is judged to produce a
greater degree of good over evil than any other alternative, and is immoral if it does
not do so” (Aronson 2001, 248). As Frankena states “an act is right if and only if it or
the rule under which it falls produces, will probably produce, or is intended to
produce at least as great a balance of good over evil as any available alternative; an
act is wrong if and only if it does not do so” (Frankena 1973, 14). It is good to note
here that, what we mean by non-moral is the absence of an ethical issue in
determining the end result (see Frankena 1973 and Aronson 2001)
According to ethical egoism “one is always to do what will promote his own greatest
good-that an act or rule of action is right if and only if it promotes at least as great a
balance of good over evil for him in the long run” (Frankena 1973, 15). This view
was held by such persons as Epicurus, Hobbes, and Nietzsche. If however, ethical
egoism or the deontological theories do not appeal to one’s self, the alternative
theories of ethics are usually sought in the theories of utilitarianism (Frankena 1973).
Utilitarianism or ethical universalism holds to the view that the “sole ultimate
standard of right, wrong and obligation is the principle of utility, which says quite
strictly that the moral end to be sought in all we do is the greatest possible balance of
good over evil (or least possible balance of evil over good) in the world as a whole”
(Frankena 1973, 34). In this case again the good and evil pertain to non-moral good
and evil. For the exception of “Ideal utilitarians” (such as G.E. Moore, Hastings
Rashdall), the traditional utilitarians have usually been hedonist, meaning that from
their perspective the moral end is concerned with the greatest balance of pleasure over
26
pain Frankena 1973, 16). The ethical judgement based on the utilitarian condition of
greatest pleasure for the greatest number (Kanungo 2001, p. 260).
Act-utilitarianism is based on the principle which “holds that in general or at least
where it is practicable, one is to tell what is right or obligatory by appealing directly
to the principle of utility or, in other words, by trying to see which of the actions open
to him will or is likely to produce the greatest balance of good over evil in the
universe” (Frankena 1973, 35). In this case George W. Bush would have to evaluate
the balance of good vs. evil that comes as a result of his actions; where the good
results and remains is much more difficult to determine. Aronson adds that actutilitarianism
is not restricted but free of rules regardless of if they are resorted to or
not (Aronson 2001, 249). According to Aronson rules may serve as a guide but do
not strictly form part of the ethical decision.
Rule-utilitarianism in much the same way as rule-deontologism emphasizes the
importance of rules in determining the morality of a particular situation. The
difference comes in with respect to deciding which rules to resort to. The ruleutilitarist
has to determine “which rules will promote the greatest general good for
everyone”, in other words it is a question of which rule has the greatest utility
(Frankena 1973, 39). In this situation George W. Bush would be able to use a specific
set of rules to determine the good vs. evil dilemma that he previously had, being a
pure act-utilitarian.
Having briefly presented the perspectives of deontology and teleology, as well as,
their different natures it is time to consider if they provide solutions to our question of
what is moral and (or) ethical leadership? Is there a single perspective presented here,
that could be applied by moral and (or) ethical leaders a deontological or a
teleological one? This seems not to be the case. It does not appear that any, “one”,
theory in itself would be able to provide guidance to the moral and ethical leader, and
Frankena and Aronson mutually agree with this (see, Frankena 1973, Aronson 2001).
For alternatives, however, Frankena and Aronson propose different solutions.
Frankena proposes his own theory of obligation, a mix of the principles of
beneficence and the principle of justice. Aronson on the other hand proposes a view
27
held by Macdonald and Beck-Dudley that “what is lacking in the traditional
deontological-teleological dichotomy is a consideration of traditional teleology, often
termed virtue ethics.” The perspective of virtue ethics and traditional teleology also
satisfies the Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership (MEDAL)
model and we will proceed into a discussion of traditional teleology and virtue ethics
as the aspect of moral leadership is addressed in the section on character.
2.6 Altruism and Egoism
Altruism and its counterpart egoism are two of the most significant concepts related to
moral principles and actions in the discussion on moral and (or) ethical leadership
(see, Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, Kanungo 2001, Ciulla 1998 & 2003). This is due
to the reason that a great many things rest on the leaders perspective (either altruistic
or egotistic), this perspective then determines for example in the case of utilitarianism
as to what a person views to be good or evil. Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) hold to
the view that the ethical dimensions of leadership should rest on altruism and that
altruism should be promoted further in organizations to attain moral and ethical
leadership. This view is not adopted by all academics in the field even though
altruism is considered a positive characteristic. Some of the most in dept discussion
on the topic can be found in Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) (see also Kanungo
2001).
In it’s simplest form we can define altruism as “a regard for the well being of others”
(Kanungo 2001, 251). The definition can be further expanded into moral altruism,
which Kanungo defines as “a helping concern for others with no regard for the cost to
one-self.” Kanungo also notes that the concept of moral altruism is cross-cultural and
universal by nature. This consideration of moral altruism as a “heritage of all
cultures” is further demonstrated by the Biblical account of the Good Samaritan cited
by Kanungo and Mendonca (1996, 92).
To convey the essence of altruistic and egotistic behaviour Kanungo and Mendonca
(1996) site the Biblical account of the Good Samaritan where different types of
behaviour can be observed:
28
A certain man went down from Jerusalem to Jericho, and fell among thieves,
which stripped him of his raiment, and wounded him, and departed, leaving
him half dead. 31 And by chance there came down a certain priest that way:
and when he saw him, he passed by on the other side. 32 And likewise a
Levite, when he was at the place, came and looked on him, and passed by on
the other side. 33 But a certain Samaritan, as he journeyed, came where he
was: and when he saw him, he had compassion on him, 34 And went to him,
and bound up his wounds, pouring in oil and wine, and set him on his own
beast, and brought him to an inn, and took care of him. 35 And on the
morrow when he departed, he took out two pence, and gave them to the host,
and said unto him, Take care of him; and whatsoever thou spendest more,
when I come again, I will repay thee. (Holy Bible, Luke 10:30-35).
As Kanungo and Mendonca (1996), (see also Kanungo 2001) point out three types of
behaviour can be identified from the account. 1) Egotistic behaviour when the thieves
intentionally harm the traveller for their own personal gain. 2) Egotistic behaviour
when the Levites show no compassion, but rather “apathy” for the man and try to
ignore the whole incident. 3) Altruistic behaviour when the Good Samaritan without
any gains on his own part stops to help and take care of the traveller. Even though we
are dealing with three different incidents in the account of the Good Samaritan, we
can, as noted above, categorise the behaviour to be either egotistic or altruistic.
Egotistic meaning benefiting one’s “self” and altruistic meaning benefiting “others”
(Kanungo & Mendonca 1996).
To fully understand altruism, however, we need to take a deeper look into its
definition. The definition of altruism has a two-fold nature as defined by social
psychologists (Kanungo & Mendonca 1996). First there is a “willingness to sacrifice
one’s welfare for the sake of another”, which is defined “as an attributed dispositional
intent to help others” (Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, 33). In other words a
purposeful inclination to help the “other” without expecting any kind of reward in
return. The second aspect of the definition concerns the “manifest behaviour and its
consequences”, the behaviour being altruistic in this case, not the intent. In other
words the nature of altruism can be understood through both the intentions, “an
internal state” and the actions a behavioural state (Kanungo & Mendonca 1996). The
internal state is important because it flows from character. Both the internal and the
external state need to exist however for the behaviour to be truly altruistic.
Considering leadership the external behavioural state is necessary from the ethical
leadership perspective, and the internal state from the moral leadership perspective.
29
Altruism is widely accepted as Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) point out, “Altruism is
highly regarded in all cultures as the epitome of sound moral principles.” Altruism is
so highly regarded that usually “Even those whose behaviour is inconsistent with this
moral principle rarely deny its validity” (Kanungo & Mendonca, 1996).
The two forms of altruism and their relationship to utilitarianism, hedonism and the
egotistic intent are well demonstrated in the following diagram by Kanungo and
Mendonca (1996), (see figure 3). The figure outlines the whole field of altruismegotism
with respect to the aspects of helping concern and harming concern.
FIGURE 3 Forms of Altruistic and Egotistic Behaviour
Source: Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, 39.
Helping concern
(benefits) for self (+)
Helping concern
(benefits) for others (+)
Harming concern
(cost) for others (-)
Harming concern
(cost) for self (-)
Hedonistic
egotism
Vindictive/
self-destructive
egotism
Utilitarian/
mutual altruism
Genuine/ moral
altruism
Apathetic
egotism
30
Continuing from altruism into determining what constitutes a morally good act from
the perspective of Kanungo and Mendonca (1996), we are offered a view different
from the earlier discussion ethics. When addressing the issue of a morally good act
Kanungo and Mendonca point to Thomas Aquinas and his three factors or criteria of a
morally good act.
According to Aquinas a morally good act consists of “(a) the objective act itself, (b)
the subjective motive of the actor, and (c) the situation or circumstances in which the
act is done” (Kanungo & Mendonca 1996, 33-4). What the objective act itself criteria
is to determine is whether the intensions of the actor are good. “Thus, to act justly is
an objectively good act, just as to murder is an objectively evil act.” Second the actor
must have good intentions, rewarding employees with stock options as part of a pay
incentive must not be done in order to make the company’s earnings look better on
the balance sheet, but for truly rewarding for good performance. Finally the situation
and circumstances must be evaluated, Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) use the
example of giving money to the poor and how this would by most be considered
morally a very good thing, however if one knew when giving the money that it would
go to buying alcohol or drugs the situation would be reversed or complicated.
Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) emphasize that to determine the moral goodness of
the act one must make sure to consider all three factors, and further the “controversies
in normative theories of ethics exist because these theories or ethical systems
emphasize one part to the neglect of the other parts.” Focusing specifically only on
one of the factors will in every case fail at closer scrutiny. Considering the issue of
taking a human life would from a purely normative perspective be readily
condemned, however if this was done in self defence responding to an assault in order
to protect one’s own life and the life of one’s family, the case is reversed. The purely
subjectivist position is not much better as the defence for one’s actions is based
merely on the persons motive in question, not taking into account that the act could be
something such as murder and the situation a case of euthanasia in a nursing home.
Finally the aspect of circumstance has to be taken into account, and the popularity of
the “situational ethics”, which uses the teleological argument of ends justifying the
means (Kanungo and Mendonca 1996). The case of the atomic bomb is used to
31
demonstrate this point, where it would be inconceivable to argue that the ends justify
the means of killing tens of thousands of innocent civilians in hopes of victory and
peace.
Kanungo and Mendonca take a very different approach to moral and ethical
leadership, an approach which is in many ways much deeper than a lot of the other
perspectives presented (in the following sections). The dept comes from the emphasis
on altruism as one of the foundations of moral behavior, followed by emphasis on
other aspects, such as, virtues (virtue ethics or traditional teleology) and a spiritual
dimension (character dimension), that are internal and both aspects of character. In
their work on moral and (or) ethical leadership Kanungo and Mendonca address both
the dimension of moral leadership and ethical leadership as outlined in the MEDAL
model (see figure 7).
Having addressed the different aspects of ethics most necessary for the foundation of
our study we will now move on to taking a closer look at the aspect of ethical
leadership and the theories of leadership behaviour. We will be taking a look at the
theories that are most often attached with ethical leadership.
32
3 ETHICAL LEADERSHIP AND LEADERSHIP STYLES
In this section we will examine the leadership theories that are central to the ethical
leadership debate. This section expands on the content of the ethical leadership aspect
of the MEDAL model mentioned earlier. The focus here is on the leadership style,
behaviour and their inter-relationship, rather than the character or a code of ethics.
The most common theories cited with respect to ethical leadership are, the theory of
transformational leadership (Burns, 1978; Bass 1985; 1999), transactional leadership,
and servant leadership (Greenleaf, 1979). Other theories that are in many occasions
proposed as having moral or ethical contribution such as charismatic leadership
(Conger and Kanungo, 1987), post-industrial leadership (Rost 1991; 1992; 1993;
1995), and directive leadership (Yukl, 1989) will also be introduced and discussed.
This section is to provide us answers and background with respect to the ethical
leadership aspect of our main research question of what is moral and (or) ethical
leadership.
3.1 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Transactional and
Transformational Leadership
The theory of transformational (moral altruism) leadership by James McGregor Burns
(1978) has established a dominant foothold as one of the main theories of ethical
leadership. The reason transformational leadership has been awarded such a major
role in moral and ethical leadership comes from the fact that the theory is founded on
a set of moral assumptions, with respect to the relationship between the leader and the
followers; transformational leadership in essence has a moral, or morally uplifting
purpose. Burns explains that in transformational leadership “leaders and followers
raise one another to higher levels of motivation and morality”, and that this is the
purpose of transformational leadership (Burns, 1978, p.20).
33
Further emphasis of the moral orientation and moral nature of transformational
leadership can be gathered from Bass’s discussion on the topic when he identifies
some features of transformational leaders:
Leaders are truly transformational when they increase awareness of what is
right, good, important, and beautiful; when they help to elevate followers’
needs for achievement and self-actualization; when they foster in followers
higher moral maturity; and when they move followers to go beyond their
self-interests for the good of their group, organization, or society (Ciulla
1998, 171).
The way the leader is able to attain the goal of a higher level of morality in both the
leader and the led according to Burns is by appealing to the higher level needs in
Maslow’s need hierarchy (see, Burns 1978). As Yukl explains, “transformational
leaders seek to raise the consciousness of followers by appealing to higher ideals and
moral values such as liberty, justice, equality, peace, and humanitarianism” (Yukl,
1989). In his theory Burns draws on the work of Abraham Maslow (needs), Milton
Rockeach (values), Lawrence Kohlberg, Jean Piaget, Erik Erickson and Alfred Adler
(moral development) (Ciulla, 1998, 17).
According to Burns transformational leadership can be implemented in any context in
the organization by any member in the organization, the influence process can be peer
to peer, leader to subordinate or subordinate to leader. As an early critique, this is
perhaps true, just as one can be a champion of Total Quality Management (TQM) in
an organization, however, to bring about significant organizational change the
initiative and support would have to come from top down. It would also be necessary
that the values of the organization be supportive of transformational leadership.
In contrast Burns compares transformational (morally altruistic) leadership to
transactional leadership (utilitarianistic) in which the leaders attempt to influence the
led is based on appealing to their self interest (Yukl, 1989). Executives exchange
monetary and status rewards to work effort and so on. The values involved (honesty,
fairness, responsibility, etc) in this equation as Yukl (1989) notes, relate to the
exchange process, and not to higher ideals as in transformational leadership.
34
Bernard M. Bass (1985) defines transformational leadership somewhat differently
than Burns (Yukl, 1989). Bass concentrates mainly on the leader’s effects on the led.
This effect consists of feelings of trust, admiration, loyalty and respect toward the
transformational leader (Yukl, 1989). Bass gives 3 ways a leader can transform his
followers: “(1) making them more aware of the importance and value of task
outcomes, (2) inducting them to transcend their own self interest for the sake of the
organization or team, and (3) activating their higher-order needs” (Yukl, 1989).
The main difference between the two scholars (Burns and Bass) and their approach to
transformational leadership is the fact that Bass does not rule out the possibility of
transactional and transformational leadership taking place in the same leader.
According to Bass a leader can use both approaches depending on which style is
appropriate for the given occasion. Burns however limits the capacity of
transformational leadership only to the so called “enlightened” leaders (Yukl, 1989).
These leaders, according to Buns, appeal to the “positive moral values and higherorder
needs of followers”. This aspect of “enlightenment” is one of the main factors
that makes Burns’s approach very morally and ethically oriented and thus very
attractive to the study in terms of moral and (or) ethical leadership.
In terms of transactional leadership, Bass gives this a much broader definition than
Burns. Burns views transactional leadership mainly as the “exchange or rewards for
compliance”, where as, Bass also includes incentives and contingent rewards to
influence motivation (Yukl, 1989). Yukl critiques the trend of separating leadership
into what he calls a “two-factor” theory, and sees in it the danger of oversimplifying
the overall leadership process. Even though this distinction has some value in terms
of clarifying and separating the two concepts (transactional vs. transformational),
there is a definite threat of oversimplifying the overall phenomena of leadership.
Kanungo (2001) follows much on the same lines as Bass by categorizing the
leadership into transactional and transformational with their specific teleological and
deontological attachments. Kanungo, however, strongly associates transformational
leadership with deontological and transactional leadership with teleological ethics.
He states that the “transactional leader is more likely to use situational and
teleological ethics whereas a transformational leader is more inclined to use universal
35
and deontological ethics” (Kanungo 2001, 263). This partially contradicts Burn’s
perspective as the transformational leader, according to Burns, is in many ways ends
oriented.
When turning to look at the deontology and teleology of transformational leadership
according to Burns, one can identify a traditional controversy in place. We can start
looking at this through a hypothetical example. Consider this. Would it be ethical to
change a few number in the balance sheet in order to save a company from becoming
bankrupt, if the company comes out triumphant in the end and everyone is saved and
nobody gets hurt. As a historian and after the fact one can maybe say, yes that was
the correct means to take if the company by a miracle does come back to life. What if
the company goes bankrupt regardless of the desperate attempts of the leadership, and
the fraud is discovered, causing the top management to be convicted of their felony.
In this case the historian and after the fact analysis would no doubt condemn this type
of leadership.
Even though by definition, Burns puts the weight on the ends and not the means in his
theory of transformational leadership, it is not necessarily as clear cut as one might
think. This can be observed from when Burns evaluates Hitler’s performance as a
transformational leader.
First, he would be tested by modal values of honour and integrity or the
extent to which he advanced or thwarted the standards of good conduct in
humanity. Second, he would be judged by the end values of equality and
justice. Lastly, he would be judged on the impact that he had on the wellbeing
of the people whom he touched (Ciulla 1998, 16).
Ciulla points out here that “Burns doesn’t consider Hitler a leader or a transforming
leader, because of the means that he used, the ends that he achieved, and the impact of
Hitler as a moral agent on his followers during the process of his leadership” (Ciulla
1998, p. 16). Here we can see that, what is called under question in the evaluation is
the “moral leadership” aspect as we have earlier defined it, with respect to character;
where ultimately the test of moral leadership is turned over to virtue ethics or
traditional teleology. This approach allows one to escape the traditional teleologydeontology
debate as both means and ends are taken into account in the evaluation of
“moral leadership”.
36
If both means and ends are not considered a weakness identified by Whetstone may
become an issue.
However, the most serious weakness of transformational leadership theory,
and the danger of its practice, is that it can be so effectively used for immoral
ends. Napoleon Bonaparte, Adolf Hitler, and Attila the Hun …were effective
transformational leaders (Whetstone 2002, 387).
The extreme focus on the ends of actions and the changes initiated by these actions,
can make Burn’s transformational leadership even appear consequentialist to some
(Ciulla 1998, 16). This kind of logic, however, carries the burden that it cannot be
evaluated until after the results of the leadership act are apparent and in the
meanwhile who is to say what the correct means are.
In terms of leadership ethics literature (Bass & Steidmeier, 1999; Kanungo &
Mendonca, 1996) it is acknowledged that authentic transformational leadership must
be based on some moral foundation” (Kanungo 2001, 257). This moral foundation in
turn must be rooted on moral character thus constituting moral leadership first and
ethical leadership second (based on our definitions in this study). The fact that
transformational leadership is deeply founded on moral assumptions makes it very
attractive for study with respect to the role of character, and as the role of character is
considered a deontological perspective is introduced.
Based on the initial interpretation of the definitions of morality and ethics the model
of Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership (MEDAL) separates
moral leadership and ethical leadership into their own categories (as well as brought
moral leadership forward as a new category; see figure 7), this however, does not
necessarily exclude transformational leadership from having strong elements of both
as a leadership style. This is one of the very reasons for the model’s introduction, as
it separates moral leadership and ethical leadership. This kind of separation can
perhaps provide help in the deontology teleology controversy of Bass (1985), Burns
(1978), Kanungo and Mendonca (1996), as well as debated issues, such as, pseudo
transformational leadership and bogus empowerment.
37
3.2 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Charismatic
Leadership
The concept of charismatic leadership has it roots in the writings of sociologist Max
Weber, who was perhaps one of the first to link the Greek word charisma (meaning
divinely inspired gift), to leadership in his studies of political leaders (Yukl 1989;
Solomon 1998, 87). Weber saw that people were influenced by unique qualities,
which the leaders seemed to possess, and it was these qualities that functioned as their
source of authority. This phenomenon thus became known as “charismatic
leadership” (for further information see also, House 1977; Bass 1985; Conger &
Kanungo 1987).
Charisma was rarely considered in relation to organizational leadership before the
1980’s, after which it gained increasing popularity due to the severe foreign
competition United States was facing, that required dramatic organizational change.
Charismatic leaders were seen as a solution for implementing changes (for example in
the car and computing industries).
After reaching the peak in its popularity in the 1980’s charismatic leadership has
attracted relatively little attention, and it has been frequently overshadowed by the
more comprehensive concept of transformational leadership (see, Burns 1979; Yukl
1989). More recently however, the concept of charismatic leadership has given
emphasis to such significant areas of study as the role of emotions in leadership, and
leadership of emotions (Solomon 1998). And even though emotions have received
very little attention in leadership literature it seem evident that “ethical leadership is
essentially based on an emotional relationship with the emphasis on charisma
replaced by the much more mundane (but no less evasive) notion of trust” (Solomon
1998). This would be true in the sense that as we acknowledge the importance of
leadership through emotions, emotions become an important aspect of moral and
ethical leadership.
38
Solomon (1998) makes the point that as we study emotions with respect to leadership
we are not talking of “the brute forces” or merely “arousal” (this being the theoretical
mindset to emotions in most cases), but about emotions that are “cognitively and
evaluatively rich and insightful. Solomon argues further that ethics does not consist
of mere rational obedience to rules, but that emotional sensitivity is needed for ethical
leadership and it is this emotional sensitivity that makes the difference not the
knowledge and rational acknowledgement of what one aught to do. Solomon uses the
example of leadership in demonstrating that “knowledge (for example, managerial
knowledge) is effective in leadership only insofar as that knowledge is in the service
of the appropriate emotions” (Solomon 1998, 93).
The perspective of emotional sensitivity applies in the same sense to moral and (or)
ethical leadership, where it is not the knowledge of moral and ethical business or
leadership that constitutes the moral and ethical leadership, but in Solomon’s words
that knowledge “in the service of the appropriate emotions.” One must remember that
most features of leadership and especially moral and ethical leadership such as “trust
and loyalty” are emotional features by nature. The concept of trust contains within
itself the idea of an emotional relationship and as Solomon states, “leadership is an
emotional relationship of trust” (Solomon 1998, 93). Thus it is also trust that
functions as a background to moral and ethical leadership.
With respect to the MEDAL model it should be noted that, in the aspect of moral
leadership the emphasis on the emotional relationship becomes even more significant
as the emotional relationship rests directly on character, rather than behavior.
3.3 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Servant Leadership
Another example of a normative leadership theory is Robert K. Greenleaf’s servant
leadership. Greenleaf came up with the idea of servant leadership after reading
Herman Hesse’s Journey to the East, which had preceded a realization by Greenleaf
during his college years of how poorly institutions and individuals were serving the
community (Greenleaf, 1977). In Hesse’s Journey to the East a character called Leo
is initially portrayed to have a role of a servant taking care of chores and needs of a
group of men who are travelling. When Leo suddenly disappears however, the group
39
immediately becomes lost and without direction. Thus Leo, even though servant by
nature turns out to be “a great and noble leader” on whom the rest of the group was
very dependent on (Greenleaf, 1977, 7).
So who is a servant leader? Greenleaf emphasises the fact that Leo was a servant first
and what he means by this is we should be servants first, whether or not we are
followers or leaders through our job description. This characteristic of being a servant
first made Leo in Greenleaf’s eyes a true servant leader. Greenleaf felt in his time of
writing that leadership was in a crisis. Taking a look at the current situation, one can
draw the same conclusions. The challenge of servant leadership and being a servant
first have increased tremendously as the culture has become more and more
individualistic and based on materialistic values.
Greenleaf acknowledges that his thesis, which states that “more servants should
emerge as leaders, or should follow only servant-leaders”, does not find tremendous
favour among the crowd. Greenleaf also felt strongly that a new moral principle was
emerging “which holds that the only authority deserving one’s allegiance is that
which is freely and knowingly granted by the led to the leader in response to, and in
proportion to, the clearly evident servant stature of the leader” (Greenleaf, 1977). In
terms of moral and ethical leadership this could be the case if the organization has
certain set moral and ethical foundations that allow Greenleaf’s principle to play out;
however in the moral and ethical flux of today’s organizations this principle is faced
with many challenges.
When looking directly to the issue of ethical and moral leadership with respect to
servant leadership, Greenleaf (1977, 26) comments in the following way on lack of
foresight:
The failure (or refusal) of a leader to foresee may be viewed as an ethical
failure, because a serious ethical compromise today (when the usual
judgement on ethical inadequacy is made) is sometimes the result of a failure
to make the effort at an earlier date to foresee today’s events and take the
right actions when there was freedom for initiative to act.
According to Greenleaf, foresight is a core requirement of a leader and if a leader
does not have foresight he is not a leader. Thus following his logic a servant leader
40
would have to possess the quality of foresight. Then acting in his/her nature as a
servant first and applying foresight would in combination constitute a type of ethical
leadership.
Servant leadership, even though thousands of years old, is a very radical idea which
keeps it away from the masses. Servant leadership also requires as Whetstone (2002)
notes, “a paradigm shift”, which may prove too much for many leaders of today. The
mantra of “serve the people” in political leadership has also lost much of its
credibility and it is also of different origin than Greenleaf’s servant leadership. Moral
and ethical leadership appear to be equally challenging and seem to appeal to the
crowd almost as much as servant leadership.
With respect to moral and ethical leadership, servant leadership measures up quite
well. Servant leadership is altruistic at heart as the concentration is put on serving
others and not self (Whetstone, 2002). A servant leader also shows genuine moral
concern for others through the qualities of a servant leader that Greenleaf has
identified as, listening, understanding, acceptance, empathy, and foresight. Greenleaf
understood these qualities to be central to ethical leadership (Greenleaf, 1977).
Servant leadership is criticized in many ways for being too unrealistic, fostering
passivity, not working in all contexts, not serving the right cause and even for a
supposed association of the word servant with the word slave and the negative
connotations it brings (Whetstone, 2002). A point is also made on normative
paradigms and on the fact that leadership based on these paradigms can prove to be
dangerous if it is teleologically trying to establish wrong ends. This relationship can
however be seen to work the other way as well, and herein lies some of the
effectiveness of servant leadership. Whetstone thus adds that a servant leader who
truly understands their calling and “strives to love her neighbour as her first priority in
business and all other spheres of life” will have less likelihood of people wanting to
take advantage of the weaknesses that the leadership style may portray them to have.
Even though one can agree with Whetstones previous statement the likelihood is only
less and there is still a chance that the weakness in leadership style may cause
someone to take advantage of it.
41
One of the reasons why servant leadership has not been adopted by many even though
it lends itself well for moral and ethical leadership purposes is the extent of
commitment and change required by the individual truly attempting this kind of
leadership. As Whetstone adds “Servant leadership does require a paradigm shift”,
and this paradigm shift into serving others as one serves themselves is very much in
conflict with today’s egocentric and assertive leadership. Perhaps for this reason the
true servant leaders of the past have existed among the non-profit organizations? The
past is behind us however, and leadership has changed in many ways by raising the
relational side and such issues as leading emotions in the post-modern context. In this
new context it could be seen that more room exists for servant leadership as the
popularity and acceptance of directive leadership diminishes.
Reflecting on what Kant’s perspective might be to servant leadership Bowie (2000)
brings up a similar concern to that of Whetstone, in that, due to the servant leadership
paradigm, the servant leader may him or herself be in conflict with Kant’s view on the
autonomy of the individual; meaning that the servant leader should not only be used
to achieve the goals of the followers but also those of him/herself. As Bowie notes
“Kant would no more permit an agent to use himself or herself as a means merely
than he would allow one to merely use another” (Bowie, 2000). This aspect roots
itself from a wrong kind of humility or low self-esteem, which Kant attaches to the
concept of servility. Bowie then raises the point that, if what Kant means by servility
is similar to the nature of a servant leader then Kant would outright reject it. However
there is a strong case to be made in favour of Greenleaf’s servant leadership
demonstrating very different values.
Servility by its connotation is in many cases indeed attached to being a slave, however
Greenleaf’s servant leaders are in no case slaves, nor do they reflect low self-esteem
or allow themselves to be used as mere means. Bowie argues that Greenleaf does
seem to endorse servility as a virtue; a fact which he bases on Greenleaf’s value of
being a servant first, and in Bowies perspective “that the great leader is seen as a
servant first” (Bowie, 2000). In the end, who is to define the true quality of the
leadership is it the outside observer or the leader him/herself to him/herself. The
outsider may qualify the individual as a servant, but only the individual can say if he
42
or she, as a leader, holds the perspective of being a servant first, whether or not this is
what is reflected to the outside.
Whether or not Greenleaf’s servant nature can be classified as servility depends on
how we and Greenleaf would define servility. Bowie also suggest that a theory of
servant leadership could be developed that would not be servile and this would satisfy
Kant. The necessity of this would again depend on how one would define servility.
It is fair then to leave the Kantian discussion of servant leadership here and conclude
that although the aspects of altruism held by servant leadership is very much in line
with Kant, further evaluation is needed to establish if servant leadership as a whole
lines up.
3.4 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Post-industrial
Leadership
Joseph C. Rost has championed a new type of leadership in the 1990’s called Postindustrial
Leadership. This leadership approach centers around the leader-follower
relationship and is seen by Rost as superior to transformational leadership. Rost
makes this claim on the basis that post-industrial leadership through the emphasis on
the relationship and the leadership process does not end up exalting the leader over
the followers. As Whetstone outlines Rost, “the leader-follower relationship is based
on persuasion rather than coercion; influence flows both from leader to followers and
from followers to leaders” (Whetstone, 2002), (See also Rost 1991; 1992; 1993;
1995). In post-industrial leadership ethical standards are constructed socially, through
an interrelationship process of the parties involved (Whetstone, 2002).
The process of socially constructing the ethical standards in post-industrial leadership
raises quite a few concerns and “if there is no right or wrong, no standard of
correctness or truth, then no on has need to repent or to accept any responsibility for
what happens” (Whetstone, 2002). This type of a situation can create uncertainty to
say the least, and lead to a “contest of power”. Whetstone also uses the example of
some American university campuses where postmodernism is prevalent among the socalled
“correctly-thinking” majority causing this majority to be able to “use any and
43
all means to convince those with minority beliefs of their politically incorrect error”
(Whetstone, 2002).
In the absence of a normative ethical perspective and principled ethics post
industrialist leadership could put any organization in a state of moral maze as
described by Robert Jackall in his book by that very name, the Moral Maze.
For Jackall the primary imperative of every organization is to succeed. This
logic of performance, what he refers to as “institutional logic,” leads to the
creation of a private moral universe, a moral universe that by definition is
totalitarian (self-sustained). Within such a milieu, truth is socially defined,
and moral behaviour is determined solely by organizational needs (Ciulla
1998, 41).
A business organization could in very much the same way create its own private
moral universe and force its members to abide by it. If this moral universe ends up
being corrupt, as appears to have been the case in Enron and Parmalat the results can
be devastative. The emphasis of the system of relationships is so strong in Rost’s
theory of post-industrial leadership, that it overtakes the worth placed on the
individual, and this raises a question of devaluing human lives and the individual at
the expense of the relationship. This could also have consequences such as the ones
outlined by Robert Jackall.
Rost also argues that it is immoral to try and change the values of the followers, to
which Burns responds that “If trying to change the values of employees of a firm to
move them into alignment with the organization’s values for the good of all
stakeholders is immoral, then it is immoral for correctional authorities to try to shift
the values of prison inmates to become constructive, law-abiding citizens” (Ciulla
1998, 179). Burns continues this thought in another instance by stating that, “Rost
would have everyone a leader but no followers in the interests of true participative
democracy” (Ciulla 1998, 179).
Whetstone (2002) challenges the idea that the product of post-industrial leadership
could be true participatory democracy, but rather a private moral universe of the
politically correct majority as already mentioned above. Further, Whetstone
emphasizes that without principled ethics it is unlikely that the ideals of Rost and
post-industrial leadership could ever be achieved. The ideals of mutual trust,
44
tolerance, and participation may ironically be reversed by the creation of one’s own
private moral universe, in which acceptance comes only to the politically correct
thinking majority (Whetstone, 2002). What is tolerance in a socially constructed
private moral universe? Either chaos (the tolerance of all things), or intolerance of
any other view.
3.5 The Moral Philosophy of Personalism and Leadership
To further reflect on leadership styles from a specific ethical perspective we will take
a look at moral philosophy of personalism and how it relates to leadership. The idea
of personalism presented here comes from the emerging school of economic
personalism at the Acton Institute. The idea was actually developed by Karol
Wojtyla now Pope John Paul II. The idea thus matured among the polish academics
and draws on the writings of French Philosopher Emmanuel Mournier. As
Whetstone notes, “In personalism there is reaction to the intellectual and social
political tendencies that appear to treat man (male and female) simply as an object of
scientific study or reduce her to an economic or socio-political function” (Whetstone
2002, p. 385). From the perspective of the organization and moral and ethical
leadership this has truly been a concern with evidence of the human individual being
considered a resource, the same as any other form of capital in an organization (fixed
or fiscal). Mourier further rejects a philosophy of things (positivism, materialism and
behaviourism) and the philosophy of abstract ideas (systems). Thus Mourier did not
consider personalism a system but a perspective or a method.
Personalism as introduced here by Whetstone takes “a position which views persons
and personal relationships as the starting point of social theory and practice”
(Whetstone 2002, 385). It is important to consider this moral perspective with
respect to ethical and moral leadership and leadership styles, because of the
significant part that the relationship plays and should play in leadership, and
especially moral and ethical leadership. The perspective of personalism also makes
the perhaps radical suggestion to some that also a “normative leadership theory
grounded in personalism should consider each human person as a spiritual and a
material creature” (Whetstone 2002, 385).
45
For a more detailed definition Whetstone has divided personalism into the
fundamental themes of phenomenological analysis concerning human action, which
include “centrality of the person, subjectivity and autonomy, human dignity, the
person within community, and participation and solidarity” (Whetstone 2002, p.
385).
From the ethical perspective of personalism and the themes, which Whetstone has
outlined, we are able to evaluate the leadership styles and how well they perform up
to the standard of personalism (Whetstone 2002, p. 385).
Theme 1: centrality of the person
The dignity and value of the human person is at the center of personalist
philosophy. Various personalists offer differing explanations of the source of
human value, but all start with a firm sense of the existence and vital
importance of human dignity.
Theme 2: subjectivity and autonomy
Personalism understands human nature as combining subjectivity and
autonomy. Each person is self-aware, consciously experiencing himself from
within. However, the human is also an objectively real ‘I,’ one conscious of
his own existence and actions. It is through subjectivity that the person
recognizes the particularity of his own objective existence, the autonomy of
his being. A person is characterized by both subjectivity and a sense of
autonomy, created with a free will to respond to heeds with responsible self
mastery.
Theme 3: human dignity
For the Christian personalist, each person is a unique, though incomplete and
imperfect, refraction of the divine image. As such, each person possesses and
is due immense dignity, being ontologically and axiologically superior to all
non-human creatures.
The dignity of the human person is displayed in his human capacity to love
sacrificially and in his faculties such as intelligence, creativity, language, and
freedom of will.
Theme 4: the person within community
A human person flourishes only in relation with other human persons. The
Christian view is that a human person, as a God-imager, is to join in genuine
community with others, based on the commandments to love God and
neighbour. Personalism does not imply individualism. It calls for
community, not just as a collection of individuals, but as a unity of persons
who relate consciously and experientially.
Theme 5: participation and solidarity
46
Human social order requires love of neighbour, a striving to bring good to the
lives of others. This requires affirmation of the right of participation by all in
society.
In terms of transformational leadership Whetstone sees quite a few problems. First,
transformational leadership does not seem to respect human dignity in the way that
the moral philosophy of personalism would expect it to. Secondly there seems to be
an inadequacy in terms of participation. Thirdly solidarity is not played out in the
way that would be satisfactory. Further criticisms of Whetstone touched on the lack
of emphasis on deontic constraints, the instrumentality and manipulativeness of
transformational leadership, the fact that it exalts the leader and finally the possibility
of tyranny by the leader (Whetstone 2002).
In Whetstones eyes servant leadership comes closest to measuring up to the moral
philosophy of personalism. There are a few concerns left however, such as, the
negative connotation of the term “servant”, the overly optimistic nature of servant
leadership, and the concern for being manipulated by followers. Even though
Whetstone sees these issues he feels that a form of servant leadership could perhaps
be developed that would be immune from the above issues and thus measure up to the
standards of personalism.
With regard to post-industrial leadership Whetstone sees further problems, from
which the centrality of the person and human dignity are the most significant issues.
As we have seen, post-industrial leadership emphasizes a system of relationships at
the expense of the individual, which is in direct conflict with personalism that
emphasises the person and their human dignity. Post-industrial leadership seems to
have further issues from the personalist perspective with lack of principles,
constraints, anthropology, and the system being dominant over the individual, as well
as, finally the conflict of reality and theory.
With respect to Whetstone’s interpretation of the moral philosophy of personalism
and leadership styles it seem that servant leadership is the best fit and could in this
context perhaps be considered to constitute moral leadership. It might be worth
noting that for servant leadership not to turn out bogus, however, the servant leader
47
has to have gone through some level of moral character development and possess the
virtues necessary for demonstrating moral leadership regardless of the leadership
style. As we may have gathered so far, it is not the specific behavioural leadership
style that is able to create moral or ethical leadership but rather moral character and
the possession of moral virtues by the leader.
3.6 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Kantian Ethics
Much on the lines of personalism, a Kantian leadership perspective holds to an aspect
of absolute equality and participation, while making the distinction that his ethics are
based purely on reason and not religious revelation (Bowie 2000, Ciulla 2003). It
seems however that even though renouncing religious revelation Kant still bases
many of his ideas on Judeo-Christian traditions having transformed them into secular
form. His formulation of the categorical imperative bears great resemblance to the
golden rule, for example. Kant is however credited with creating a moral system
available for anyone willing to reason. The foundation of this moral system rests on
the notion that one should have “respect for the dignity of all human beings” (Ciulla
2003).
Kantian leadership carries with it a deontological view where the morality of actions
does not depend on ends but on the intention and good will of the one committing the
act. Behaviour is to be based on principle and doing what is right instead of what
makes people happy. Kant does not even believe in morality of actions resulting in
happiness, which is true for example in the ethics of Aristotle. Kant notes that
making the right choice may hurt, initially and after as well (Ciulla 2003).
Bowie (2000) proposes a set of principles in terms of Kantian leadership that are
based on Kant's concept of a kingdom of ends, meaning that “all rational beings stand
under the law that each of them should treat himself and others never merely as means
but always at the same time as an end in himself” (Ciulla 2003). According to this
kingdom of ends, Bowie points out a Kantian way to transform an organization into a
kingdom of ends. The principles are as follows:
48
1 The leader should consider the interests of all the affected stakeholders in
any decision it makes.
2 The leader should have those affected by the firm’s rules and policies
participate in the determination of those rules and policies before they are
implemented.
3 It should not be the case that the leader always gives the interest of one
stakeholder group priority.
4 When a situation arises where it appears that the humanity of one set of
stakeholders must be sacrificed for the humanity of another set of
stakeholders, the leader cannot make the decision on the grounds that there is
a greater number of people in one stakeholder group than in another.
5 Every leader must in cooperation with other in the organization establish
procedures to ensure that relations among stakeholders are governed by rules
of justice.
According to this set of principles the leaders are to first respect every individual and
through a moral point of view take other into consideration (Bowie 2000). Secondly,
the leader is to use participation as a transformative tool to turn followers into leaders.
Thirdly, the leader has a task to ensure that participants are not used for receiving
profits without getting any benefits in return. The fourth principle is to establish an
anti-utilitarian condition and finally the fifth principle ensures that in the case of
disagreement things will be settled on the basis of justice.
Bowies main argument with (against) the above leadership principles based on
Kantian ethics is that autonomy should be the foundation and basis of a Kantian
leader. He notes that the above criteria could have universal application while
meeting the principle of kingdom of ends.
3.7 Ethical Leadership Perspective to Directive Leadership
The traditional directive leadership styles of autocratic, benevolent autocratic,
consultative, participative, consensus, and laissez-faire type leaders are not overly
discussed with respect to moral and ethical leadership (Aronson 2001). This is mostly
due to the fact that they are not seen as having the potential to raise the moral
competence of followers, as is the case with transformational leadership.
49
This brings us back to the key question with respect to the source of ethical and moral
leadership. Is the source the leadership style (some leadership styles are defined in to
be moral in essence), or is the leader independent of what kind of leadership style they
are using. Style may not necessarily be the determining factor of a leader’s source of
ethics “but rather on his or her level of moral development or the extent to which the
influence process employed is motivated by ethical values” (Aronson 2001, 248).
Could it be considered that the source of ethical and moral leadership can be isolated
to the moral character of the leader, and that it is this character that enables some and
obstructs others to lead morally and ethically? This is a suggestion that I am willing
to make, while acknowledging that even though this character may be the enabling
factor (the heart of moral leadership) in the equation of moral and (or) ethical
leadership, it does not alone constitute for moral and ethical leadership. The moral
character clearly needs to be supported by other factors such as a suitable leadership
style and an otherwise developed Human Factor HF (see, figure 6).
The above suggestion would open up the opportunities of moral and ethical leadership
to some of the more traditional leadership styles as well (e.g. transactional, directive,
etc.), since “moral” and “ethical” leadership would be defined in a new way.
The ability to identify moral leadership, regardless of the context of the leadership
style it takes place in, would be very significant especially in the cross-cultural
context of global managers. This is a context where several different leadership styles
may have to be used, and are in use, depending on the cultural background of the led.
Leaders who also find it hard to fully step into the role of a transformational, or
servant leader could make gains in terms of moral leadership through character
development, taking away the burden of a specific leadership style.
The flipside of the coin is most likely true, in that one cannot be a servant leader or a
transformational leader without developing one’s character and virtues (in accordance
to virtue ethics). This equation is the main reason for the development of what we
have come to know as bogus empowerment (Ciulla 1998) and pseudotransformational
leadership (see also Bass 1999).
50
3.8 Models of Ethical Leadership
Few models focusing purely on moral and (or) ethical leadership exist. To give an
idea of the constructs involved Aronson’s model of ethical leadership is introduced
here to help us with the defining of the moral and ethical elements involved from a
different perspective (see figure 4). Aronson’s model takes an approach that focuses
on the aspects of directive, transactional and transformational leadership (Aronson
2001, 250). The model outlines two ends of the ethical leadership spectrum one high
in moral development (MD), and the other low. Aronson makes a point, however,
that the level of moral development is not a direct determinant of leadership style,
more the other way. Meaning that the ethical leadership style is the one which
reflects the ethics and values adopted by the leader, and thus may result in being
transformational.
What is the resulting factor for moral and (or) ethical leadership is also a point we
want to raise and emphasise in this study. We have adopted a similar and perhaps
even a stronger position here with respect to the order in which the phenomena of
moral and ethical leadership takes place and this is why the MEDAL model (see
figure 7) proceeds first into morals and then into ethics and leadership styles. To
develop the order further we feel that it is necessary to start with moral leadership,
proceeding into ethical leadership and thus leadership styles, finally an aspect of an
ethical code can be considered. For the leadership to have credibility (regardless of
the style) the moral and ethical development has to take precedence over the
leadership aspect. The level of moral development in Aronson’s model is measured
by the level of egotism versus altruism, a view which is also held by Kanungo and
Mendonca (1996), see also figure 3). At the high end of moral development and
altruism Aronson has outlined an ethical leadership zone. Above this zone Aronson’s
model shows the ethical leadership styles and the corresponding ethical theories,
according to the dimensions of Transformational Leadership (TF), Transactional
Leadership (TA), and Directive Leadership (DR).
51
When contrasting the model to the Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with
Leadership (MEDAL) presented at the results section of this study, we note that this
model fits well with in the MEDAL. Aronson’s model describes the midsection of
MEDAL which outlines the aspect of ethical leadership bringing into it some moral
characteristics. Aronson makes the separation with respect to moral development,
which in the MEDAL is expanded further to include areas such as, the aspect of
character (retaining a moral, spiritual and a human abilities dimension, see next
section) along with altruism. One of the key contributions of MEDAL is in fact the
emphasis of character and the overall moral development possible through character
that has the ability to result in moral and ethical leadership. We feel that the aspect of
character and moral development are of such significance that they need to be
considered separately.
52
FIGURE 4 A Model of Ethical Leadership by Edward Aronson
Directive
• Autocratic – Despotic
• Egotistical
Artificial transformational
• Pseudo-transformational
• Personalized charismatic
High transactional
• Contingent reward
Nondirective
• Laissez-faire
Low transactional
• Laissez-faire
Low TF
TA
High TF
TF
DR
MD
Transformational Leadership = TF
Transactional Leadership = TA
Directive Leadership = DR
Note: Items in bold face refer to leadership styles
Low moral development (MD)- egotism
Source: Aronson 2001, 250
(Continues)
53
Figure 4 A Model of Ethical Leadership by Edward Aronson (Continued)
Directive
• Ethical Egoism
• Benevolent autocratic-Nurture-task
Genuine transformational
• Deontological
• Authentic transformational
• Socialized charismatic
High transformational
• Utilitarian
• Contingent reward
• MBE-active
Nondirective
• Participative
• Consensus
Low transactional
• MBE-passive
Low TF
TA
High TF
TF
DR
Ethical Leadership Zone
MD
Transformational Leadership = TF
Transactional Leadership = TA
Directive Leadership = DR
Note: Items in bold face refer to leadership styles- items in italics refer to corresponding ethical theory
High moral development (MD)- altruism
Source: Aronson 2001, 250
54
4 MORAL LEADERSHIP AND CHARACTER
Character, and in moral and ethical leadership, moral character to be more specific, is
an aspect that has not received adequate attention. This fact is also evident in this
interpretative study of concepts, and flows from the necessity to define moral and
ethical leadership differently. As a result of the interpretation done in this study, we
have come to conclude that character is very much at the heart of moral and also
ethical leadership in the same way as Ciulla (1998) has defined “ethics” to be at the
heart of leadership.
Up to this point we have defined and introduced various topics in morality, ethics and
leadership, which have enabled us to bring light to our task of understanding what
moral and (or) ethical leadership is? As a result of the descriptive interpretative study
of concepts (see, section on method for more details) done in this study we have,
however, proceeded in developing the concepts further finally resulting in a
comprehensive focus on the aspect of character as the heart of moral leadership.
Developing the aspect of character and moral leadership is one of the main
contributions of this study (both for academics as well as for the practitioner). As a
result of the conceptual development, the MEDAL model has been introduced in this
study for the first time (see the results section); it is one of the first models to clearly
separate moral leadership and ethical leadership into different categories and to
outline the focus of those categories. It is clear that in the future the MEDAL needs to
be further researched and subjected to empirical study, but the purpose in this study
was to give a starting point for the field of moral leadership and to be able to develop
and discuss the different aspects with increased clarity and distinction. We will now
proceed into the development of the aspect of character and its significance to moral
leadership in this section.
As was identified, there is a case for character to be the heart of moral and ethical
leadership and as this is acknowledged it becomes a question of what constitutes
moral character and how it can be developed to foster this moral and ethical
leadership. This notion of character supports the common observation, where in
55
terms of leadership ethics one knows what is right and ethical, but is not necessarily
going to do the right thing. Thus it is not the ignorance of what is right or wrong or
what is moral or ethical leadership, but a weak character. It is doubtful that the
accountants of WorldCom, Enron, or Parmalat, so skilfully would have made a
mistake in the books that made the company initially look much better.
In this section we will first take a look at the definition of character; second traditional
teleology and virtue ethics are introduced as part of moral leadership theory; and
finally the aspect and importance of character is addressed with respect to
personalism, different leadership styles and the Human Factor Theory.
Frankena (1973) notes that “morality in the sense indicated is, in one aspect at least, a
social enterprise, not just a discovery or invention [or code] of the individual for his
own guidance. Like one’s language, state, or church, it exists before the individual,
who is induced into it and becomes more or less of a participant in it, and it goes on
existing after him.” This makes the very important distinction, that morality with
respect to leadership is more than a set of principles or guidelines, and that a leaders
morality and his/her moral leadership is innate, a part of his/her being.
When the results of leadership turn out bad it is usually not a problem of “ethics”,
meaning the set standards or code of right and wrong and the principles of human
duty (refer to section 2 for the indebt definition). But rather this is a problem of
morals that relate to the persons moral backbone, which we can refer to as character.
The standards (ethics) exist, even in the pseudo moral leader’s world, but the issue is
that the standards have not become morals and thus have not become absorbed into
the persons character.
To take a look at an exact definition of character (as was done for morals and ethics in
section 2), here is the Oxford English Dictionary (OED) definition of character:
The face or features as betokening moral qualities; personal appearance. Obs.
The sum of the moral and mental qualities which distinguish an individual or
a race, viewed as a homogeneous whole; the individuality impressed by
nature and habit on man or nation; mental or moral constitution.
56
Moral qualities strongly developed or strikingly displayed; distinct or
distinguished character; character worth speaking of (Oxford English
Dictionary OED 2004).
As we can see from the Oxford English Definition there is a strong emphasis on moral
and mental qualities and moral qualities that are specifically developed and displayed
as part of character.
Edwin M. Hartman in Blackwell Encyclopedic Dictionary of Business Ethics also
defines character to have a close connection with a moral element, which is dependent
on the virtuousness or viciousness of the person (Werhane & Freeman 1997). This
virtuousness or viciousness is then reflected as good or bad character. Another aspect
that Hartman raises in terms of the strength of the character is that it can be observed
through the strength (or the lack of it) of one’s resolve in one’s values. This aspect is
key as we develop the concept of character later on with respect to the Human Factor
(HF) theory (see section on HF).
Having taken a closer look at the definition of character it is important to shift the
focus to how character inter-relates with leadership and moral leadership. The
following quotation by Al Gini demonstrates well the centrality of character with
respect to leadership, and more specifically moral leadership.
The quality and worth of leadership can only be measured in terms of
what a leader intends, values, believes in, or stands for-in other words,
character. In Character: America’s Search for Leadership, Gail Sheely
argues, as did Aristotle before her, that character is the most crucial and
most elusive element of leadership. The root of the word “character”
comes from the Greek word for engraving. As applied to human
beings, it refers to the enduring marks or etched- in factors in our
personality, which include our inborn talents as well as the learned and
acquired traits imposed upon us by life and experience. These
engravings define us, set us apart and motivate behaviour [these can be
understood as the HF dimensions introduced later on]. In regard to
leadership, says Sheely, character is fundamental and prophetic. The
“issues [of leadership] are today and will change in time. Character is
what was yesterday and will be tomorrow.” Character established both
our day-to-day demeanour and our destiny. Therefore, it is not only
useful but essential to examine the character or those who desire to lead
us (Gini 1998, 37).
Having touched on the link between character and leadership and its importance one
may go a step further into the aspect of moral development and development of moral
57
leadership. Kanungo (2001) notes this when he states that, “Above all, leaders’
personal moral development results from character formation or cultivation of values
through the practice of harbouring altruistic intent, engaging in virtuous acts, and
interpreting social situations consistent with their worldviews.” This notion of a
leader’s personal moral development through character formation is an extremely
important aspect of moral leadership, because it carries the implication and reality that
moral leadership can be learned, or unlearned for that matter. Having said this, it
would be important to pay more attention to the area of moral leadership and the
centrality of character as we have defined it here in this study. The significance of
character and the aspect of moral development bring further justification for moral
leadership to stand separate from ethical leadership and leadership ethics. Kanungo
and Mendonca (1996, 5) go as far as stating that “schools ought to regard character
formation as the core element of their mission. This would seem to be particularly
necessary in the case of management education”.
Mendonca (2001) outlines the dimensions of ethical leadership in three ways “a) the
leader’s motives, b) the leader’s influence strategies, and c) the leader’s character
formation”. However, he makes a very similar point with respect to character
formation and its relationship to the other two dimensions by clarifying that “the
leader’s motives and influence strategies are the result of the leader’s character.” In
terms of the character formation Mendonca has developed a model on self
transformation of leaders. The model has four dimensions in terms of the sources of
1) self-transformation of leaders, 2) principles of ethical power, 3) competencies of
managerial resourcefulness, 4) cardinal virtues and personal mastery (see figure 5).
This model also demonstrates well the centrality of character in the self
transformation process of a leaders and the importance of cardinal virtues.
58
FIGURE 5 Sources of Self-Transformation of Leaders and Followers
Source: Mendonca 2001, 273.
Of course this aspect of moral development is not new (though somewhat ignored) as
Aristotle already was one of the main champions of emphasising the role of character,
and character formation through practice and habit as part of an individuals moral
development (Kanungo 2001, p. 260). Aristotle also notes that character should be
made a central element of moral virtue. The next section will deal with the aspect of
virtue and virtue ethics more specifically, along with traditional teleology.
4.1 Traditional Teleology and Virtue Ethics
As we mentioned earlier utilitarianism focuses on the maximization of good or
pleasure, while minimizing the bad or pain. The utilitarian does this independently
and without the evaluation of what might be the right or wrong desires (Aronson
2001, 248-9). Traditional teleology or virtue ethics on the other hand, “seeks the most
favourable outcome, but within the context of virtues such as prudence, courage,
Principles
of Ethical
Power
Competencies of
Managerial
Resourcefulness
Cardinal virtues
Personal Mastery
Purpose Perspective Persistence Patience
Goal-directed
Orientation
Proactive
Analytical
Problem-focused
Persevearance
Emotional
Equanimity
Shared Vision Objective
Assesment
Focused
Energies
Creative
Tension
Pride
Practice of Examination of Conscience
Justice Prudence Fortitude Temperance
59
temperance, and justice, thus avoiding immoral behaviour.” (Aronson 2001, 250; see
also, Werhane & Freeman 1997, 436-7; Kanungo & Mendonca 1996, 87).
Even though generally deontology and teleology are held to be mutually exclusive
this need not be so. Academics such as Brady (1985) propose that they could actually
be complementary. With respect to traditional teleology or virtue ethics, this is
considered to be the case. Aronson states that traditional teleology is “not
deontological in its method of evaluation, but it does operate within what may be
called a deontological moral framework providing the best of both deontology and
teleology” (Aronson 2001, 250). Kanungo (2001) points out that “Both Socrates and
Plato considered virtuous acts to be the basis of morality.” This is a direction worth
investigating since the current mainstream ethical theories previously do not provide
us with viable alternative to be applied in terms of moral leadership.
The four cardinal virtues of prudence, justice, fortitude and temperance were
formulated by Plato (Mendonca, 2001). The word cardinal comes from the Latin
word for hinge. According to Mendonca (2001) this is “because around them hinge
human acts or practices that, acquire moral significance when these practices are
consistent with the moral principles implicit in the cardinal virtues” (Mendonca,
2001). Realising the significance of character in moral and ethical leadership one
could consider moral and ethical leadership also to be hinged around the virtues of
prudence, justice, fortitude and temperance.
Prudence
Prudence as defined by the Oxford English Dictionary (OED) means the “Ability to
discern the most suitable, politic, or profitable course of action, esp. as regards
conduct; practical wisdom, discretion” (Oxford English Dictionary 2004).
The practice of prudence according to Mendonca (2001) demands constantly
assessing the specific situation in which decisions are made in the light of what he
calls “right standards”. Mendonca points out that a leader who practices prudence
will not partake in, or abdicate responsibility to commit unethical behaviour. The
60
prudent person will make an effort to seek out information so as to be able to make
sound judgements regarding both his/her actions or the actions of ones followers.
Justice
Justice is defined by the Oxford English Dictionary as “the quality of being (morally)
just or righteous; the principle of just dealing; the exhibition of this quality or
principle in action; just conduct; integrity, rectitude” (Oxford English Dictionary,
2004).
The practice of being just thus requires the leader to make sure that he/she is giving
others what they are due (principle of just dealing). The just dealing or giving other
what they are due “includes whatever others might need to fulfil their duties and
exercise their rights as persons, that is, right to life, to cultural and moral good,
material goods, and so on” (Mendonca, 2001). According to Mendonca (2001) the
just leader should seek to balance out the rights of all the different stakeholders in a
fair manner. Thus giving fair treatment to customers, suppliers, government,
community and owners.
Fortitude
Fortitude is defined by the Oxford English Dictionary as the “moral strength or
courage. Now only in passive sense: Unyielding courage in the endurance of pain or
adversity” (Oxford English Dictionary, 2004).
For the leader fortitude is “the courage to take great risks for an ideal that is
worthwhile” (Mendonca, 2001). A leader possessing the moral strength or courage
seeks to overcome obstacles by also demonstrating perseverance and endurance to do
what he/she holds as good or noble.
61
Temperance
Temperance is defined by the Oxford English Dictionary as “the practice or habit of
restraining oneself in provocation, passion, desire, etc.; rational self-restraint” (Oxford
English Dictionary, 2004).
In the leadership context temperance “involves distinguishing between what is
reasonable and necessary and what is self indulgent” (Mendonca, 2001). Temperance
further reaches to the spheres of allocating one’s time, effort and resources effectively
and efficiently so as not to overindulge in hedonistic behaviour.
Rosenthal brings up an important point when defining virtue ethics in that a
distinction needs to be made between moral virtue as a state, rather than behaviour.
According to Aristotle “virtue ethics is concerned with the cultivation of virtuous
traits of character as among the primary function of morality”, and further that virtue
is a state or disposition rather than actions. This separation has to be made for the
reason that it is possible for an individual to commit virtuous acts, without having
virtuous traits of character, but acting on some other motive. If then the actions or
behaviour was used as the determinant one would inevitably reach incorrect
conclusions as to the moral character of the individual. Here again one can see the
separation, which is also apparent in the model developed in this study (MEDAL),
where moral leadership (with its main focus on character) is separated from ethical
leadership (with its main focus on behaviour) for the very reason mentioned above.
If the above distinctions are not made one could end up in a situation well described
here by Eugene Heath, a philosophy professor at the State University of New York,
she states that “Business ethics in this country [USA] has little to do with ethics…It
has a lot to do with public policy” (Wipperfurth 2002). She goes on to state that
“Enron was politically correct. What does that have to do with how you treat other
people?” The point we are making here is that it is easy to be fooled by politically
correct virtuous behaviour and pseudo transformational leadership, which has no
moral dept in terms of character and moral leadership. This is not to say that this
separation is controversy free, especially in today’s social context placing such a high
value on political correctness. To an extent one can identify a post-industrial
62
leadership climate from Eugene Heaths comments, where as long as one remains
politically correct they are able to do whatever they want regardless of the moral
foundation (or lack of it) of the motives, acts and behaviour.
To further develop the aspect of character we will proceed in the next section by bring
forth a more recent theoretical perspective developed by an economist Senyo
Adjibolosoo, called the Human Factor Theory (HF). Adjibolosoo’s HF theory
provides a more detailed analysis of the personality characteristics of an individual
and in this way helps shed light on some aspects of character formation (Adjibolosoo
1995b).
4.2 Character Development and the Human Factor HF
Having established the importance and centrality of character formation as the key
element of moral development of leaders, we will proceed to outlining and
introducing another theoretical model called the Human Factor (HF) Theory
(Adjibolosoo 1995b). This theory is from outside the moral and (or) ethical
leadership field of research, but it is perhaps one of the only recent theories pertaining
to personality characteristics and character in a comprehensive way. Due to its
uniqueness we rely heavily on it in this section. The theory is also in many cases
attached to moral and ethical leadership in the field of international development (see
Adjibolosoo 1995, 1998, 1999 and 2000). The HF theory is one of the only theories
with this kind of a unique focus on the individual’s character qualities, and the aspects
of moral and spiritual capital and human abilities (expanded on later).
The Human Factor (HF) theory has come about as a result of research with a specific
focus on the Less Developed Countries (LDC’s). This factor is significant due to the
fact that these countries are in many cases experiencing a significant moral and ethical
leadership crisis making the theory even more relevant for our purposes. However
let’s first take a look at and establish the different dimensions of the HF theory.
The HF theory takes a different approach to the issues of personal, institutional and
national development. The HF concentrates on the character of the individual and the
63
qualities that are comprised by that character. According to Adjibolosoo the HF
“constitutes the intangible asset or liability of humanity”, and in much the same way it
constitutes an asset or a liability to the post-modern business organization. He also
notes that, “properly developed HF animates, guides and encourages people to
perform specific functions that are required of them in their tasks assigned by
society”. These are some of the components that contribute to the significance of the
HF and how it bears relevance to the constructive approaches of the global
community. Before going any further, it is necessary to expand on the composition of
the six primary components of the HF (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 33).
FIGURE 6 The Human Factor Composition
Source: Adjibolosoo 1995b, 34-36.
Spiritual Capital
Spiritual capital is the aspect of the human personality that possesses the
capability to be in tune with the universal laws and principles of human life.
These laws and principles state the truth regarding how humanity must live if
it is to achieve the “good and abundant life” in every regard. Spiritual capital
provides insights into the human condition that the five senses are unable to
grasp and bring forth. It furnishes the individual with more advanced
capabilities to create, to invent, to innovate and to develop techniques and/or
procedures for dealing with the limitations of the human intellect
(Adjibolosoo 1995b, 34)
Spiritual Capital Aesthetic Capital
Human Capital Human Abilities
Human Potentials
Moral Capital
The Human Factor
64
Stephen Covey, in his book “The Seven Habits of Highly Effective People”, makes a
notion that “the spiritual dimension is your core, your centre, your commitment to
your value system” (Covey 1989, 292). This aspect is of crucial importance as the
strength of the moral character is dependent on the degree of commitment to one’s
values (Werhane & Freeman 1997, 436-7). This means that the spiritual dimension
must be taken into account and further studied as part of moral leadership, since the
strength of the moral character rests directly on this spiritual dimension.
With respect to universal principles, Covey has identified, that the six major religions
of the world “all teach the same basic core beliefs-such principles as ‘ you reap what
you sow’ and ‘Actions are more important than words’” (Covey 1991, 95).
According to Covey one can identify universal beliefs in the areas of “fairness,
kindness, dignity, charity, integrity, honesty, quality, service, and patience.” These
principles are also in agreement with the moral and spiritual capital of the human
factor and its moral constituents.
Adjibolosoo agrees with Covey in that spiritual capital is the centre of human
efficiency and effectiveness directly in relation to an individuals “job performance
and task accomplishment”, (not just in moral sense but overall) (Adjibolosoo 1995b,
34). A society ignoring the aspect of spiritual capital development will not be able to
provide “a humane and productive environment to its inhabitants.” Spiritual capital
will encourage an individual to seek out truth in their will to carry out tasks
effectively. Doing what is true according to Sandin is “the identifying mark of
spiritual wholeness” (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35). Spiritual education should teach
obedience to the truth and the significance of the spiritual dimension to humanity.
Adjibolosoo quotes Paul Nash in that “If education does not result in spiritual [capital]
formation, it is [a] bad investment” (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35). Kanungo and
Mendonca hold a similar view to character development where they see character
formation as one of the main missions of educational institutions (Kanungo &
Mendonca 1996, 5).
Kanungo and Mendonca (1996) also emphasize the importance of the development of
the spiritual dimension in stating that “spirituality is an integral part of ethics. It
provides sustenance to the leader’s efforts to develop a moral character possessed of
65
inner strength and resourcefulness, and to create a moral environment in the
organization.” this is to say that if one seeks to be a moral and ethical leader one must
possess some degree of spiritual capital. As one will see through our investigation of
the composition of the Human Factor it is not enough to have spiritual capital to be a
moral and (or) ethical leader, but that all the different parts play a specific role.
Spiritual capital is the starting point to the character development of a moral and (or)
ethical leader and one could even go as far as to say that, without spiritual capital
there will be no moral leadership.
Larry Spears (1996), the executive director of the Robert K. Greenleaf Centre for
Servant-Leadership also states that one of the applications of servant leadership
“involves its use in programmes relating to personal and spiritual growth”, he further
emphasises “the ideas of M. Scott Peck, Parker Palmer, Ann McGee-Cooper and
others who have written and taught on the expansion of human spirit and potential.”
One can clearly identify how significantly Greenleaf emphasises the importance of
spiritual capital as one of the characteristics of a servant leader. And as Whetstone
(2002) quotes Rabbi Wayne Dosick “if we uplift the human spirit, we can bring
meaning and value to the modern marketplace” (for a definition of spiritual see,
Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, 87; or Concise Oxford English Dictionary OED).
Moral Capital
Moral capital represents habits and attitudes of the human heart that are
based on principles relating to right and wrong. It refers to the qualities
individuals possess that lead them to conform or not to conform to ethical
principles and standards of conduct. The voice of the human conscience
usually functions as part of a person’s moral capital. The constituents of
moral capital are diverse and include integrity, humility, sincerity, charity,
courtesy, patience, faithfulness, sensitivity, purity, honesty, kindness, justice,
tolerance, forgiveness, flexibility, collegiality, truthfulness, fidelity and many
others. (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35)
According to Adjibolosoo moral capital is essential even to the course of economic
development, as it equips individuals with the ability to perceive “universal laws as
the primary foundation for acceptable or unacceptable human behaviour and action”,
the acceptable and unacceptable behaviour in this case referring to moral and amoral
behaviour respectively (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35). In this context Adjibolosoo speaks
66
of individuals, but the same can be applied to leaders and the relevance is actually
increased if we are to consider moral capital with respect to leadership.
The importance of moral capital (whether talking of leaders or individuals), as an
element of the personality characteristics of the HF, is without a doubt irrefutable.
When the focus shifts to leadership the HF characteristics and their balanced
development becomes even more important, specifically in the areas of moral and
spiritual capital and human abilities. Kanungo (2001) makes this point well in his
reflection on the topic when he states that, “Both academic scholars and management
practitioners recognize that all forms of leadership behaviour gain their legitimacy and
credibility from the leader’s moral standing and integrity. When the leader’s moral
integrity is in doubt, then all attempts by the leader to influence followers however
noble, well crafted, and articulated fail to move them to achieve organizational
objectives” (Kanungo 2001, p. 258). In agreement with Kanungo the HF theory also
emphasises that everything rests on the leaders moral standing (moral capital) and
integrity (one of the constituents of moral capital). The HF theory however goes a
few steps deeper with a well defined spiritual dimension and an established
relationship between the moral and spiritual dimensions.
The importance of moral leadership based on a developed moral character and moral
capital rather than simply ethics is also evident from Covey’s concept of moral
compassing (Covey 1991, 94). Covey points out that in terms of leadership it is
extremely important to have a moral compass and not to be dependent on “moral”
maps, which maybe subject to constant changes. Further Covey points out that this is
even more critical in environments of rapid change where maps go quickly out of date
if they ever were valid in the first place, leaving the leadership frustrated and
confused.
The concept of moral compassing and “moral” maps is very much in accordance to
what we have established in this study. We have made the point that moral leadership
has to be able to stand alone, with its specific focus on character and behind that
character a spiritual dimension or core. This dimension of moral leadership and its
elements are to act as the moral compass on which the leader can rely and rest at times
white water and change. It has to be acknowledged that the leader cannot depend on
67
the “moral maps” of ethical leadership in terms of behaviour and style, and leadership
ethics of code of conduct alone, but needs a developed moral compass and moral
capital enabling for moral leadership from which ethical leadership will also follow.
Covey gives a few reasons as to why a moral compass is better than a “moral” map
and of significant value to corporate leaders:
• The compass orients people to the coordinates and indicates a course or
direction even in forests, deserts, seas, and open, unsettled terrain.
• As the territory changes, the map becomes obsolete; in times of rapid
change, a map may be dated and inaccurate by the time it’s printed.
• Inaccurate maps are sources of great frustration for people who are trying
to find their way or navigate territory.
• Many executives are pioneering, managing in uncharted waters or
wilderness, and no existing map accurately describes the territory.
• To get anywhere very fast, we need redefined processes and clear
channels of production and distribution (freeways), and to find or create
freeways in the wilderness, we need a compass.
• The map provides description, but the compass provides more vision and
direction.
• An accurate map is a good management tool, but a compass is a
leadership and empowerment tool.
After having discussed the two core elements of moral and spiritual capital we
will move on to the other human factor components starting with aesthetic
capital.
Aesthetic Capital
Aesthetic capital implies the possession of a strong sense of and love for
beauty. It includes a strong passion for music, drama, dance and for other
artistic capacities (imagination, inventiveness, innovation and creativity are
strong components). (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35)
Aesthetic capital when adequately developed will allow individuals “the ability to be
appreciative of beauty and truth and the skills to judge between what is good and
acceptable and what is not (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 36). Even Bass (see section on
transformational leadership) identifies “aesthetic capital” as one of the characteristics
of a transformational leader, when he states that transformational leaders “are truly
transformational when they increase awareness of what is right, good, important, and
beautiful; when they help to elevate followers’ needs for achievement and selfactualization;
when they foster in followers higher moral maturity; and when they
68
move followers to go beyond their self-interests for the good of their group,
organization, or society” (Ciulla 1998, 171). And even though not necessarily the
core of moral leadership, aesthetic capital is still significant in terms of the leader’s
personality characteristics.
Human Capital
Human capital is usually defined as the know-how and the skills that are
acquired by men and women, are used to enhance human productivity, and
have market value. Human capital is made up of technical, conceptual,
intellectual, analytical and communicational skills. An example of properly
developed human capital is the individual with knowledge (gained from the
study of academic disciplines, human experiences, revelation, etc.),
understanding, astuteness and intelligence or aptitude. Physical well-being
and emotional health are integral parts of human capital, as well.
(Adjibolosoo 1995b, 36)
Even though Human Capital is only one out of the six aspects of the entire HF, it is
usually the focus as we educate, recruit and train individuals in society and in
institutions; this should be revised. As we have identified earlier in several occasions,
education that does not result in character development can be considered a poor
investment and in terms of management education this should be revised to include
moral character development and moral leadership.
Human Abilities
Human abilities constitute the power or capacity of an individual to
undertake projects competently or effectively perform tasks requiring mental
and physical effort. These are the acquired or naturally endowed human
abilities necessary to, but not alone sufficient for, successfully performing
assigned tasks and/or effectively undertaking and engaging in productive
activities. Human abilities enable people who possess them to execute
excellently given duties and functions when these abilities are working in
conjunction with other components of the acquired human capital. Human
abilities include wisdom, vision, commitment, judgement, responsibility,
reasoning, competence, interest, motivation, credibility, human energy,
optimism, perseverance, endurance, self-control, objectivity, reliability,
adaptability alertness and many other such human attributes. (Adjibolosoo
1995b, 36)
The human abilities completes a powerful core triangle of moral capital,
spiritual capital and human abilities that lies in the heart of the human factor
way of character development. The aspect of human abilities is also a truly
powerful dimension that completes the aspects of moral and spiritual capital,
69
dimension that are noted by Covey (1989, 1991), Kanungo and Mendonca
(1996).
Human Potentials
“Human potentials are the human talents that may or may not be harnessed
and employed for human-centred development. These may be referred to as
the unused dimensions of the HF.” (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 36)
Finally we have the aspect of human potentials, an area of talents not harnessed yet,
but which makes us humans so amazing. In terms of moral and (or) ethical leadership
the dimension of human potentials is especially exiting as this is the aspect that lies
behind our ability to demonstrate moral leadership and apply transformational
leadership, raising the follower morally and ethically to a new level and making them
leaders.
4.2.1 Developing the Human Factor Concept
According to Adjibolosoo, the HF qualities are constantly changing, either
accumulating or decumulating depending on the situation of the individual in his or
her life. This is both a challenge and an opportunity. A challenge in the sense that to
avoid decumulation one has to constantly keep on developing one’s HF, and an
opportunity in the sense that something (training, self-development, mentoring) can
actually be done in the area of HF development and the HF with respect to moral
leadership. Adjibolosoo also proposes that even after an individual ceases to exist
the indirect influence of their qualities and characteristics may still remain
(Adjibolosoo 1995b).
Adjibolosoo also warns about combining spiritual and moral capital as one. This is
due to the fact that even though well-developed spiritual capital will result in the
increase of moral capital, the inverse will not hold true, meaning that even extensive
development of moral capital does not necessarily result in the accumulation of
spiritual capital. According to this thinking we imply “that spiritual capital
encompasses moral capital in its entirety within the individual” (Adjibolosoo 1995b,
37). From what we have established in terms of moral leadership we would also note
that both spiritual and moral capital are necessary and even though separate entities,
70
extremely interdependent on each other for their successful functioning. The dilemma
of combining spiritual and moral capital as one is very similar to the dilemma related
to combining moral and ethical leadership as one under ethical leadership, which for
various reasons already cited would be less than ideal.
Adjibolosoo also prioritizes the qualities so that spiritual and moral capital must be
acquired previous to the others, in order for the others to function correctly. He also
notes that even though “spiritual capital can be sufficient alone for the effective use of
both human and aesthetic capital, moral capital is not always sufficient alone”
(Adjibolosoo 1995b, 37). This is a question of identifying the correct type of value
system based on principles rather than on feelings or values, which is also the
perception of Covey (1991). People who have founded their lives on “universal
ethical [moral] principles and standards are individuals who are able to work and
successfully complete tasks without extensive supervision,” resulting in efficient and
productive outcomes. Adjibolosoo quotes Swindoll at this point who writes that these
are people “who model excellence when no on is looking or for that matter when half
the world is looking.”
A society with well-developed HF will enjoy substantial increases in both efficiency
and productivity without increasing investment in monitoring its individuals. As
previously mentioned, principle-centered individuals need little supervision to be
productive. According to Adjibolosoo the “labor force will be driven by the universal
principles engendered by and embedded in the society’s acquired spiritual, moral
capital and human abilities” (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 37). In this respect human capital
development alone is not sufficient to produce productive and efficient individuals for
society as we noted earlier. Adjibolosoo emphasizes that an individual can be
extremely developed in the aspect of human capital (with respect to their skills and
knowledge), without the ability to function effectively in business or society or social
institutions. This is easier to observe in developing countries where the level of
corruption may be relatively high often proving fatal to projects even though the
human capital seems to be in place. With a closer scrutiny we can easily identify
similar examples in the “more developed world”, (i.e., ethical, environmental, social
and moral cases).
71
For someone to be able to make effective use of their human and aesthetic capital they
must first acquire the necessary spiritual and moral capital, which will enable them to
do so, as excellence cannot be achieved any other way (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 37). It is
possible for individuals to lack the necessary spiritual and moral capital and still
perform due to the amount of human capital that they have acquired. This
performance, however, will not be anything like their potential would allow them, if
they would have the necessary spiritual and moral capital to back it up. It is the welldeveloped
spiritual and moral capital that creates an environment in which our unique
human abilities can excel and perform to their optimum. A society, which only
focuses on the development of human and aesthetic capital, while neglecting the other
HF aspects, will not develop a workforce rich in human abilities. The neglect of
spiritual and moral capital can also lead to the misuse of the already acquired human
abilities, and even though spiritual and moral capital is difficult, if not impossible to
measure accurately, they are reflected by the individual, both internally and externally
(see also Kanungo and Mendonca 1996, 87).
A workforce rich in human abilities will only be attained through a holistic approach
to HF development. If not done holistically, the lack of HF can lead to economic
underdevelopment, continuing business losses and business failures (Adjibolosoo
1995b, 38). In Adjibolosoo’s experience many developing countries have focused
heavily in developing the human and aesthetic capital, while ignoring the other HF
aspects, resulting in very limited development. In some what could be considered exdeveloping
countries, such as, the Asian tigers (e.g. Singapore). The HF development
effort has been more extensive and a pattern can be seen in the extent of HF
development and the country’s economic success.
Many developed countries such as the USA, Canada and UK have paid serious
attention to their HF development in the past, and due to this investment in HF, have
also attained high economic growth and development (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 38). This
does not ensure growth and development in the future, however, due to the dynamic
nature of the HF mentioned earlier. HF can be both gained and lost, and as mentioned
already we are at all times in our life either in the state of developing our HF or
depleting it. Adjibolosoo perceives a possibility of the developed countries living off
the HF legacy that they have accumulated over the years, first resulting in the
72
depreciation of spiritual and moral capital, and further in the decline of human
abilities. This would seriously affect the economic and industrial development in the
long run. “In this regard, the United States, Canada, the United Kingdom, Japan,
Germany and many others run the risk of falling victim to the syndrome of HF
underdevelopment unless they take the necessary steps to ensure that HF development
remains a priority in their industrialization programs” (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 38).
4.2.2 Impact areas of the Human Factor
All institutions consist of three basic factors, physical (real-estate), financial (cash
flow), and human (individuals). These factors are usually referred to as capital (i.e.,
financial or human capital). One can literally take away the physical and financial
factors and still have a functioning institution, but you cannot take away the human
factor, this would make the institution irrelevant and non-existent. The other capital
(financial and physical) can be considered to be fairly uniform in quality to all,
whereas the human capital and especially the human factor are not. As we earlier
state this can be better observed when contrasting LDC’s between themselves, as well
as, with respect to some more developed countries. It is thus the human capital and
developed human factor that for the most part defines the organization. Further the
human factor in institutions is clearly the key to their existence and to their efficient
and productive functioning. The institutions in our society consist of, and are
operated by, individuals in various positions. At the end the direction of any
institution is determined by its leadership and the success of its goals and objectives is
determined by the sum total of its individuals. If a society expects to proceed
according to its plans and reach its goals and objectives, it is dependent on its
individuals to demonstrate responsibility, integrity, accountability and commitment,
which will enable the society to uphold justice, political harmony and a disciplined
labour force (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 33).
One of the key qualities is the ability to utilize acquired knowledge and information
effectively in problem identification and solution (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 33). If we
desire the process of knowledge and information acquisition, and its implementation
73
in problem identification and solution to be effective, the individuals must reflect the
following qualities:
The people must exhibit responsibility in leadership, dedication through
commitment, resourcefulness in the use of available resources, resilience and
tolerance in adversity, inventiveness, innovativeness and imagination in
relation to their chosen vision and accountability through service (Adjibolosoo
1995b, 33).
In the case that these qualities and characteristics are non-existent, especially in
leadership, it is difficult to grow and develop the social, political and economic
infrastructure and institutions (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 33).
As was mentioned previously it is important to realize the limitedness of mere
“human capital” development in individuals, since human capital is only one of the
six components of the entire HF.
Human capital is limited to developing the essential know-how and skills of an
individual through education and training, and even though an essential component of
the HF it will not bring about productivity alone. The direction our society has taken
has been to emphasize human capital in the sense of the definition given earlier, while
the other aspects of the HF are often forgotten as we focus on developing human
capital.
Adjibolosoo makes it clear that for individuals to be productive other qualities beyond
human capital are needed. These unique human qualities and/or characteristics, as
Adjibolosoo calls them, are necessary to further economic and social progress. These
qualities would include attributes such as, “integrity discipline, dedication,
responsibility, diligence, insightfulness, accountability and the like”, which do not
come about through human capital development alone, but through the development
of spiritual and moral capital, as well as, human abilities (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 34).
Edwin P. Hollander also makes this point quoting a work of McCall, Lombardo and
Morrison (1987), done on some 400 executives concerning the issue of “derailment”
(Hollander 1998, 57). As a result it was discovered that, the ones “who failed to reach
their expected potential were more often found to lack skills in relating to others, not
74
technical skills.”, which goes to show the importance in leadership of the other
dimensions of the Human Factor in addition to human capital.
Transformational leadership as described by Burns has in many ways the same effects
on the organization as does the development of the Human Factor (Hollander 1998).
One of these areas of significant influence would be the need for supervision. When a
organization consists of individuals that have developed Human Factor or who have
through their leadership developed their Human Factor there is much less need for
supervision in terms of the followers. The same would be true in the case of
transformational leadership where the moral fibre of the followership is developed or
raised, thus also leading to a lower need of supervision. Eventually in both cases it
would also be possible that the HF development or the moral development at the end
results in the follower becoming a leader.
The primary importance of the HF concept rises from the extent of its impact. This
impact reaches all areas of society including social, political and economic
institutions, starting with the institution of marriage and family and ending with
international political institutions. If an individual is unable to show leadership in
his/her marriage and family, one of the most basic institutions of life, how do they
expect to contribute through leadership in an organization with an even more complex
organizational culture?
Leaders should at all times promote and develop good work ethic and social ethos.
By ethos we mean “the fundamental character or spirit of culture…the underlying
sentiment that informs the beliefs, customs or practices of a group or society”
(Adjibolosoo 1999, 16). The ethos is what distinguishes one people group from
another. The ethos also acts as a foundation for developing people’s ethical system,
where by ethics we mean “the body of moral principles subscribed to by a group of
people (i.e., societies, organizations, countries, etc.). These principles, rather than
feelings or values, guide, guard, and direct the behaviour of leaders and other
individuals in society (Adjibolosoo 1999, 16).
The main consequence, as a result of the lack of developed HF in individuals would
be the decline of “personal accountability, integrity, trustworthiness, responsibility,
75
and commitment to principles of life and work”, as discussed in the section dealing
with the composition of the HF (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 38). This lack of developed HF
in individuals of a nation would then be reflected throughout its institutions and
organizations, as the lack of the above personality characteristics.
The lack of adequate moral and spiritual capital in individuals can be observed from
their behaviour in political, economic and social institutions (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 38).
This handicap often results in placing the pursuit of personal interests of money, fame
or being elected, before the interests of the institution or organization. This is neither
wanted nor ideal leading to underdevelopment. According to Adjibolosoo, there is
nothing wrong with an individual being influenced by such factors as “money,
culture, prestige and self-actualisation”; it is when, due to the lack of spiritual and
moral capital, they become the centre of attention for the individual. This
phenomenon is unfortunately very frequent in today’s culture which has shifted
towards economic imperialism and a cult of self-worship (Mendonca 2001, 267).
The lack of developed HF is most visible in nations where the satisfaction of the basic
physical needs of life are hard to come by, driving individuals to satisfy these needs
more strongly (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 38). With the lack of a developed HF in
leadership, and especially the missing spiritual and moral capital there is a danger for
negative rent-seeking by individuals when given the opportunity (e.g. Enron,
Parmalat, WorldCom, etc.), leading to corruption, abuse, and in extreme cases death.
This will stunt possible economic growth and the development of social welfare.
When spiritual and moral capital are developed adequately the focus will shift from
the fleeting short-term rewards to “the long-lasting principle of human life (such as
integrity, justice, equity, fairness, love, sanctity of life, ect.)” (Adjibolosoo 1995b,
38).
The lack of Human Factor development plays a significant role in terms of the failure
of ethical theories such as rule utilitarianism, which states that “persons [need to]
conform to sets of rules to act in a way which will again give the highest degree of
good for the greatest number of people” (Aronson 2001, 249). However if the
persons involved do not have a developed Human Factor or moral character it is very
unlikely that conforming to such rules will take place. As a result it will not matter
76
how foundational the rules are in terms of ethics and how well accepted they are by
individuals, the system will fail to function in the long run.
77
5 DISCUSSION AND RESULTS
There is no question of whether both moral and ethical leadership are required, and as
Aronson (2001, 245) notes “CEO’s are obliged to set a moral example for
organizational members and to demarcate the constant striving for increased profits
from those activities which may be detrimental to the values of society in general.”
Aronson brings up the important aspect of society in general and the significance of
the effects of moral and ethical leadership on society. This is very true and an
important aspect to remember as it is not only the organization that benefits when
development of moral and ethical leadership takes place, but everyone. Kanungo puts
this in the following way “In ethical leadership, the motives, acts, and characters of
leaders result in the moral development of both the leader and the followers, which in
turn serve the interests of their organizations and society at large” (Kanungo 2001,
260).
It is also evident that society at large is in need of moral and ethical development due
to the many threats it is facing. Mendonca raises some of the most significant ones,
which we already mentioned earlier in the notion that, “Economic imperialism
demands that money and material possession be the primary yardstick to measure
success and failure in every sphere of human life, and therefore be valued more than
everything else in society” (Mendonca 2001, p. 267). We are continually seeing these
types of challenges and the susceptibility of leadership to their lure.
One of the concrete challenges of moral leadership on the executive level is
compensation, which does not and has not for several years reflected the performance
of top management. Also the fact that top management is paid such high salaries,
especially in the United States, where a CEO may receive a salary of 100 times plus,
that of the average worker, calls their overall leadership role into question (not just
moral and ethical). Hollander notes that even though “leaders are recognized as
needed, they also may be resented for having a position of authority that accords them
special benefits, as seen now for instance in the contempt many hold for members of
Congress” (this would hold true in Finland as well), (Ciulla 1998, 55). As Hollander
78
also notes, it may be increasingly hard for leaders who perform poorly and are still
rewarded with higher pay to foster good followership, loyalty and trust. Also any
kind of participation, teamwork, or credibility of having concern for their followers is
most likely lost.
Among these challenges, turmoil, confusion and a need of moral and ethical
leadership it is important for us to clearly understand the meanings of moral and (or)
ethical leadership, so as to better understand the problem areas and root causes. By
this study we have attempted to bring some clarity to the concepts and their meanings
and even some of the inter relationships. In the following we will briefly outline the
results.
5.1 What is Moral and (or) Ethical Leadership?
So after all this interpretation and analysis what is moral and (or) ethical leadership?
Are they the same or are they different? As a result of this interpretative study of
concepts we have discovered and established first of all, that moral leadership is and
should be a separate independently-considered entity. We would argue that without
this separation and having moral leadership mixed into ethical leadership, the clarity
of the different concepts and their meaning is reduced to a level where they are
increasingly difficult to work with. Based on the findings of this study a model on the
Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership (MEDAL) has been
realized (see figure 7). This has resulted in the ability to clarify the existing concepts
and to establish some of the relationships and levels.
In terms of what is moral leadership we have discovered that the focus is centred on
character and more precisely moral character from which the moral leadership results.
With deeper study on character it became evident that character is directly dependent
on a spiritual dimension or core for the strength of its moral principles. From this
combination flows moral leadership which is reflected by such constituents “as
integrity, humility, sincerity, charity, courtesy, patience, faithfulness, sensitivity,
purity, honesty, kindness, justice, tolerance, forgiveness, flexibility, collegiality,
truthfulness, fidelity” to name a few (Adjibolosoo 1995b, 35). The leader
79
demonstrates moral leadership already by merely possessing these qualities and
having them associated with his character. Further it was established that formation
of moral character and moral development can be acquired through learning and self
development in the specific areas in question, which makes moral leadership into a
practical dimension.
What is left for ethical leadership then? As a result of the study we established that
ethical leadership’s main focus is behaviour and more specifically ethical leadership
behaviour and ethical leadership styles. In this debate there is a strong focus on moral
philosophy of leadership (ethics), and the leadership styles (transformational,
transactional, charismatic, servant, post-industrial and directive leadership) are
reflected on through this philosophy. As we have established, it is hard to say exactly
which one of these leadership styles could be considered closest to ethical leadership.
The main debate circles around transformational, transactional and charismatic
leadership, with good arguments for many of the others. It is clearly not possible here
to go with one or the other and the attempt here has focused more on bringing out the
moral and (or) ethical dimensions in these leadership styles rather than develop
arguments for one or the other.
The above debate however, is somewhat irrelevant because even if a specific
leadership style was to be established as being the most ethical and moral it has a very
limited capacity to produce any practical results. Knowing how one should behave
does not necessarily result in that behaviour, as the initiation for the behaviour is not
internal (value and virtue based) but merely informative and cognitive. If we are to
start with the behavioural approach (ethical leadership) we are coming at our aim of
moral and ethical leadership in reverse order with limited results. There is a strong
case in favour of an argument in which development of moral character and moral
virtues are to be addressed first. If the moral character and moral virtues are
developed first, moral and ethical leadership behaviour can follow, however this does
not work the other way. Studying and learning ethical leadership styles and behaviour
will not necessarily result in moral character and moral virtue development. If ethical
leadership theory assumes to contain moral character and virtue development it needs
to be clearly laid out that this is the case. As we have noticed that individuals lacking
in developed moral character and moral virtues have attempted ethical leadership
80
styles such as transformation and charismatic leadership only to find out that they
have gone horribly wrong, with their behaviour resulting in pseudo-transformational
leadership and unethical and sometimes dangerous charismatic leadership. We are
not by all means saying that behavioural study of ethical leadership styles is totally
irrelevant, but rather that it is only one area of the moral and ethical dimensions
associated with leadership, which are outlined in the MEDAL model as a result of this
study (see figure 7).
One of the main results of this descriptive interpretative study of concepts has been
the realization of the Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership
(MEDAL) model (see figure 7). The MEDAL model has been outlined according to
the objectives of descriptive interpretive study of concepts by Takala and Lämsä
(2001) starting with 1) intuition, 2) new concepts and imagination, and 3) reflective
thinking, In the MEDAL model moral leadership is awarded its own dimension
along with ethical leadership, and thirdly a dimension of leadership ethics focuses on
the code of ethics, situated as part of the philosophical dimension. A leadership
dimension with levels on trait leadership, behavioural leadership and contingency
leadership are also included in the model, but not expanded on in this study due to
having to demarcate. We will note however, that a developed moral leadership
dimension provides the ability for the leader to function and contribute in any of these
different leadership styles or approaches. This hypothesis could also prove fruitful for
possible further research.
This categorization of the concepts can be observed from the following figure 7,
where the model of Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership
(MEDAL) is outlined. In accordance to the MEDAL this study has taken an
introductory look at the leadership dimensions. The ethical dimension is looked at in
terms of the leadership styles and theories related to those styles, after which a more
in-depth look has been taken into the area of moral leadership and the aspect of
character. The dimension of leadership ethics (code of leadership ethics) will
however not be looked at in this study, as it was not central to our primary objective.
81
FIGURE 7 Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with Leadership MEDAL
Moral Leadership
”do”
Ethical Leadership
”we”
Leadership ethics
”should”
Focus on moral
character and moral
virtues as the center
of Moral Leadership
Conduct.
Focus on moral
philosophy of
leadership, as the
center of Ethical
Leadership
Behaviour.
Focus on the
development of
moral philosophy
of leadership and
code of ethics.
Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with
Leadership MEDAL
Moral Character:
-Focus on character
in moral leadership.
Ethical Behavior:
-Focus on leadership
behavior and
leadership style in
ethical leadership.
-
Code of Ethics:
-Focus on the code
of leadership
ethics.
Practical Aspect Philosophical Aspect
Moral Dimension Ethical or Ethics Dimension
Contingency Leadership Level: situations and contexts.
Behvioural Leadership Level: behaviours and styles.
Trait Leadership Level: traits, characteristics, and qualities.
Leadership Dimensions
Moral and Ethical Dimensions
Moral and Ethical Dimensions Associated with
Leadership MEDAL
82
It is not to say that the above categorisation will solve all problems with respect to
discussing morals, ethics, and leadership and certainly there are issues to be sorted
out. A distinction with good enough fit, however, may save the common terminology
from being overtaken by confusion, especially in the eyes of the practitioner.
5.2 Validity, Reliability and Credibility
When talking about validity we are asking the question, is the study answering and
measuring the question it was set out to answer originally and how well does it do
this. First we would say that, yes the study does answer the question that it was
originally set out to answer, and this is done by using the best academic sources as a
foundation. The use of the best and most relevant academic references is especially
important when using interpretative study of concepts as a method, and this was taken
into account. Second for the sake of validity (and at some cost to reliability which in
this case is to be expected) descriptive interpretative study of concepts was used as a
method and a lens. This approach allowed us to reach the best validity, meaning it
gave us the methodological flexibility to answer the question we had intended to
answer to the best of our ability.
In terms of reliability we would ask for example the question that, if someone else did
and interpretative study of concepts on same research question; would they receive
the same result. We are confident that if the study was repeated the same constructs
would be found to exist, which we have been outlined here. This is due to the fact
that these constructs flow out of the main sources in the field of moral and ethical
leadership, and the globally available definitions on terminology. It would be
expected though that the study, being qualitative in nature and using interpretative
study of concepts as a method, would not produce an identical result as the method
allows for the creation of something new, which (as in this study) has to be confirmed
by further research in that specific area. In this study that area would be the
constructs of moral leadership and its relationship to character. Even though the
sources are selected and read with a view that is as objective as possible, the authors
own subjectivity cannot be escaped from in this study; as is the case with most
qualitative studies. It has to be acknowledged that it is not possible to do an
interpretive study such as this one and meet the criterion of objectivity. This means
83
that in someone were to repeat the study they would also have to deal with their own
subjectivity (sex, culture, education, etc.) and it is likely that this would be reflected in
the results of the study. It also has to be noted that no-one is able to read all the
material available due to limited resources and the limited nature of the pro graduate
study. However we are confident here that the essential material has been covered
and in terms of reliability another researcher would select the same main sources in
the field of moral and ethical leadership.
In terms of the credibility of the study and the possibility for evaluation, the reader
should be able to follow up on the reasoning used and criticize it; this being the major
concern in terms of credibility in this kind of a hermeneutic study. Visual mapping
such as the MEDAL, as well as the Conceptual Framework of the Study (see figure 2)
should make it easier to understand the logic and reasoning behind the interpretive
analysis. Criticism in this case would be very welcome, as at this stage many of the
concepts are under development and would need criticism and further research. We
especially hope that further research on the constructs of moral leadership does take
place and that the concepts overall are developed to attain better clarity.
5.3 Further Recommended Research
As this study has been a descriptive interpretative study of concepts there are various
possibilities for further research. The main continuation to this study would be an
expansion on the constructs of moral leadership and the role of character. Empirical
data and study based on that data would also be necessary on the aspects of moral
leadership.
Further study could also be done now on the separation of moral and ethical
leadership more specifically, having established their difference. The problematics of
ethical leadership and its behavioral dependence could also be addressed in this kind
of a study.
Finally the code of leadership ethics, which was delimited out of the actual
assessment due to the size of the topic, is an area of possible further research. Further
84
empirical study could be done in terms of the existing code of leadership ethics as
well as, it necessary development.
85
6 CONCLUSION
The main objective of the study was to answer the questions what is moral and (or)
ethical leadership and are the concepts the same? A further aim was to clarify the
different concepts regarding and surrounding moral and (or) ethical leadership. The
reasons cited for this study included, the topic being new in the Finnish context,
current demand in the topic area and the shift of the global focus in leadership
research towards moral and ethical aspects.
The attempt of the study has been to bring a theoretical contribution to the field of
moral and (or) ethical leadership; first, by making a distinction between the different
concepts of moral leadership (specifically pertaining to character and its result in the
conduct of the leader), ethical leadership (specifically pertaining to the leaders actions
and the principles of human duty), and leadership ethics (specifically pertaining to the
code of ethics). And second, by synthesising and summarizing the main theories and
approaches to moral and (or) ethical leadership; a way in which the whole study
functions as a single answer to the main research question.
The method selected for use in this case was descriptive interpretative study of
concepts aimed at increasing the understanding of a concept or concepts (Takala &
Lämsä, 2001). The objective of this type of a study was “to find, describe and
interpret the entity of meanings” (Lämsä 2003). In this descriptive interpretative
study of concepts the researcher aimed at “describing and clarifying the significations
given to a concept” which in this case is moral and (or) ethical leadership (Lämsä
2003).
In the definitional stage the attempt was to define or redefine concepts such as
ethic(s), moral and leadership. This started by looking at the leadership definitions
and history of leadership. A working definition for leadership was selected as
“Leadership is an influence relationship between leaders and followers who intend
real changes that reflect their mutual purpose” (Ciulla 1998). After the leadership
focus, the concepts of morality and ethic(s) were looked at in more detail after which
86
it was decided that there was such significant difference that a distinction had to be
made.
After terminology had been addressed the focus shifted towards the main theories of
ethics and their relation to moral and (or) ethical leadership. Following the main
ethical theories the main behavioural theories of ethical leadership were reviewed to
establish a perspective on the behavioural leadership ethics dimension. Lastly in
terms of the study the concept of moral leadership and character was expanded and its
significance was looked at reflecting on both virtue ethics and the Human Factor HF
theory.
The attempt was to clarify the conceptual framework of moral and (or) ethical
leadership, which was accomplished within the objectives and aims set. The hope of
the author is that while attaining the objectives and aims, the study has also been as
educational to the reader as it has been to the author himself. Hopefully the paper has
been provoking some thoughts, developing opinions, providing intellectual
stimulation, and perhaps even moral and ethical inspiration.
87
7 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Adjibolosoo, S. 1995a. The Human Factor Development. Scandinavian Journal of
Development Alternatives 12, 139-149.
Adjibolosoo, S. 1995b. The Human Factor in Developing Africa. Westport, Conn.:
Praeger.
Adjibolosoo, S. 1998a. Global Development the Human Factor Way. Westport,
Conn.: Praeger.
Adjibolosoo, S. 1998b. International Perspectives on the Human Factor in Economic
Development. Westport, Conn.: Praeger.
Adjibolosoo, S. 1999. Rethinking Development Theory and Policy: A Human Factor
Critique. Westport, Conn.: Praeger.
Adjibolosoo, S. 2000. A Human Factor Approach to Human Resource Management
and Organization Development. Review of Human Factor Studies 6, 1-13.
Anttila, P. 2003. Tutkimisen taito ja tiedon hankinta. Metodix.
Aronson, E. 2001. Integrating Leadership Styles and Ethical Perspectives. Canadian
Journal of Administrative Sciences 18, 244-256, Halifax.
Bass, B. 1999. Ethics, Character, and Authentic Transformational Leadership
Behavior. Leadership Quarterly 10, 181-217
BBC News. 2003. Parmalat in Bankruptcy Protection. 30.12.2003.
Bowie, N. 2000. A Kantian theory of leadership. Leadership & Organization
Development Journal 21, MCB University Press.
Brady, N.F. 1985. A Janus-Headed Model of Ethical Theory: Looking Two Ways at
Business/Society Issues. The Academy of Management Review 10, 568-576.
Burns, J. 1979. Leadership. New York, Harper Torchbooks.
Conger, A & Kanungo, R. 1987. Toward a behavioural theory of charismatic
leadership in organizational settings. Academy of Management Review 12, 637-647.
Ciulla, J. 2003. The Ethics of Leadership. Belmont, Wadsworth/Thomson Learning.
Ciulla, J. 1998. Ethics: The Heart of Leadership. Westport, Praeger.
Ciulla, J. 1995. Leadership Ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, Vol 5, Issue 1.
88
Covey, S. 1989. Seven Habits of Highly Effective People. New York: Simon and
Schuster.
Covey, S. 1991. Principle Centered Leadership. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Drouillard, S. & Kleiner, B. 1996. “Good” leadership. Management Development
Review, Volume 9, Number 5, MCB University Press.
Frankena, W. 1973. Ethics. Prentice-Hall, New York.
Gini, A. 1998. Moral Leadership and Business Ethics, in J. Ciulla (ed.), Ethics: The
Heart of Leadership. Westport, Praeger, 27-49.
Greenleaf, R. 1977. Servant Leadership: A Journey into the Nature of Legitimate
Power and Greatness. New York, Paulist Press.
Hollander, E. 1998. Ethical Challenges in the Leader-Follower Relationship, in J.
Ciulla (ed.), Ethics: The Heart of Leadership. Westport, Praeger, 49-61.
Holy Bible: Old and New Testament, 1983. King James Version, Charlotte: North
Carolina, PTL Publishing.
Kanungo, R. 2001. Ethical Values of Transactional and Transformational Leaders.
Canadian Journal of Administrative Sciences 18, 257-265, Halifax.
Kanungo, R & Mendonca, M. 1996. Ethical Dimensions of Leadership. Sage
Publication. London.
Kanungo, R. & Mendonca, M. 2001. Ethical Leadership and Governance in
Organizations: A Preamble. Canadian Journal of Administrative Sciences 18, 241-
243, Halifax.
Lämsä, A-M & Takala, T. 2003. Interpretative Study of Concepts. Metodix,
www.metodix.com, 20.5.2003.
MacIntryre, A. 1984. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. London, University of
Notre Dame Press.
Mendonca, M. 2001. Preparing for Ethical Leadership in Organizations. Canadian
Journal of Administrative Science 18, 266-276, Halifax.
Oxford English Dictionary (OED Online). 2004. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Rost, J. 1991. Leadership for the Twenty-First Century. New York, Warner Books.
Rost, J. 1992. Leadership: A postindustrial approach. European Management Journal
10, 193-201.
Rost, J. 1993. Leadership in the New Millenium. Journal of Leadership Studies 1, 92-
110.
89
Rost, J. 1995. Leadership: A Discussion About Ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly 5,
129-142.
Solomon R. 1998. Ethical Leadership, Emotions, and Trust: Beyond “Charisma”, in J.
Ciulla (ed.), Ethics: The Heart of Leadership. Westport, Praeger, 87-107.
Takala T. & Lämsä A-M. 2001. Tulkitseva käsitetutkimus organisaatio- ja
johtamistutkimuksen tutkimusmetodologisena vaihtoehtona. LTA 3, 371-390.
Townsend, R & Bennis, W. 2003. Leader II. Journal of Business Strategy 24, 48.
Trevino, L. Hartman, L. & Brown, M. 2000. Moral Person and Moral Manager: How
Executives Develop a Reputation for Ethical Leadership. California Management
Review 42.
Washbush, J, Clements, C. 1999. The two faces of leadership. Career Development
International, Volume 4, Number 3, MCB University Press.
Werhane, H.P. & Freeman, R.E. 1997. Encyclopedic Dictionary of Business Ethics.
Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Oxford.
Whetstone, T. 2002. Personalism and moral leadership: the servant leader with a
transforming vision. Business Ethics: A European Review, Oxford, Blackwell
Publishers Ltd.
Wipperfurth, H. 2002. Enron Scandal Touches Off Boom in Ethics Education.
Crain’s New York Business 18.
Yukl, G. 1989. Leadership in Organizations. 2 ed. Eaglewood Cliffs. Prentice-Hall.

Postingan populer dari blog ini

Tata Ibadah Bidston Syukur Keluarga Bp Suwondo

LITURGI ULANG TAHUN PERKAWINAN KE 50 BP.SOEWANTO DAN IBU KRIS HARTATI AMBARAWA, 19 DESEMBER 2009

Tata Ibadah Bidston Syukur Keluarga Bpk/Ibu Karep Purwanto Atas rencana Pernikahan Sdr.Petrus Tri Handoko dengan sdr.Nining Puji Astuti GKJ Ambarawa, 3 Mei 2013